rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com Open in urlscan Pro
192.0.78.12  Public Scan

Submitted URL: http://rowlandpasaribu.files.wordpress.com/
Effective URL: https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com/
Submission: On January 06 via api from US — Scanned from DE

Form analysis 6 forms found in the DOM

GET https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com

<form action="https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com" method="get">
  <div class="content">
    <input type="text" class="textfield searchtip" name="s" size="24" value="">
    <input type="submit" class="button" value="">
  </div>
</form>

GET https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com/

<form role="search" method="get" id="searchform" class="searchform" action="https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com/">
  <div>
    <label class="screen-reader-text" for="s">Search for:</label>
    <input type="text" value="" name="s" id="s">
    <input type="submit" id="searchsubmit" value="Search">
  </div>
</form>

GET https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com

<form action="https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com" method="get"><label class="screen-reader-text" for="cat">Categories</label><select name="cat" id="cat" class="postform">
    <option value="-1">Select Category</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="177">Art</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="115257861">Coffee Ebook</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="36603056">Coffee Economics</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="1233955">Coffee History</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="71165883">Comments and Reflection</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="2578915">DISCUSSION PAPERS</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="161441707">JURNAL PREDATOR</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="133232">KOLEKSI BUKU</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="37395423">Kopi Nusantara</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="73409107">Legal and Free Ebook</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="690764298">Namoura Coffee</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="703796593">Namourapedia</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="25146">PERKULIAHAN</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="1784">Resources</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="70932323">Result and Research</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="3457">Social</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="1">Uncategorized</option>
    <option class="level-0" value="131916">WORKING PAPERS</option>
  </select>
</form>

POST https://subscribe.wordpress.com

<form action="https://subscribe.wordpress.com" method="post" accept-charset="utf-8" data-blog="30193205" data-post_access_level="everybody" id="subscribe-blog">
  <p>Enter your email address to follow this blog and receive notifications of new posts by email.</p>
  <p id="subscribe-email">
    <label id="subscribe-field-label" for="subscribe-field" class="screen-reader-text"> Email Address: </label>
    <input type="email" name="email" style="width: 95%; padding: 1px 10px" placeholder="Email Address" value="" id="subscribe-field" required="">
  </p>
  <p id="subscribe-submit">
    <input type="hidden" name="action" value="subscribe">
    <input type="hidden" name="blog_id" value="30193205">
    <input type="hidden" name="source" value="https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com/">
    <input type="hidden" name="sub-type" value="widget">
    <input type="hidden" name="redirect_fragment" value="subscribe-blog">
    <input type="hidden" id="_wpnonce" name="_wpnonce" value="4e995146bc"> <button type="submit" class="wp-block-button__link"> Follow </button>
  </p>
</form>

POST https://subscribe.wordpress.com

<form method="post" action="https://subscribe.wordpress.com" accept-charset="utf-8" style="display: none;">
  <div class="actnbr-follow-count">Join 275 other subscribers</div>
  <div>
    <input type="email" name="email" placeholder="Enter your email address" class="actnbr-email-field" aria-label="Enter your email address">
  </div>
  <input type="hidden" name="action" value="subscribe">
  <input type="hidden" name="blog_id" value="30193205">
  <input type="hidden" name="source" value="https://rowlandpasaribu.wordpress.com/">
  <input type="hidden" name="sub-type" value="actionbar-follow">
  <input type="hidden" id="_wpnonce" name="_wpnonce" value="4e995146bc">
  <div class="actnbr-button-wrap">
    <button type="submit" value="Sign me up"> Sign me up </button>
  </div>
</form>

<form id="jp-carousel-comment-form">
  <label for="jp-carousel-comment-form-comment-field" class="screen-reader-text">Write a Comment...</label>
  <textarea name="comment" class="jp-carousel-comment-form-field jp-carousel-comment-form-textarea" id="jp-carousel-comment-form-comment-field" placeholder="Write a Comment..."></textarea>
  <div id="jp-carousel-comment-form-submit-and-info-wrapper">
    <div id="jp-carousel-comment-form-commenting-as">
      <fieldset>
        <label for="jp-carousel-comment-form-email-field">Email (Required)</label>
        <input type="text" name="email" class="jp-carousel-comment-form-field jp-carousel-comment-form-text-field" id="jp-carousel-comment-form-email-field">
      </fieldset>
      <fieldset>
        <label for="jp-carousel-comment-form-author-field">Name (Required)</label>
        <input type="text" name="author" class="jp-carousel-comment-form-field jp-carousel-comment-form-text-field" id="jp-carousel-comment-form-author-field">
      </fieldset>
      <fieldset>
        <label for="jp-carousel-comment-form-url-field">Website</label>
        <input type="text" name="url" class="jp-carousel-comment-form-field jp-carousel-comment-form-text-field" id="jp-carousel-comment-form-url-field">
      </fieldset>
    </div>
    <input type="submit" name="submit" class="jp-carousel-comment-form-button" id="jp-carousel-comment-form-button-submit" value="Post Comment">
  </div>
</form>

Text Content

MR. ROWS NAMOURA COFFEE

Kopi & Buku

 * Home
 * Tentang Saya
 * PERKULIAHAN
   * METODE RISET
   * PENGANTAR BISNIS
   * ILMU BUDAYA DASAR
   * PENDIDIKAN PANCASILA
   * ANALISIS INVESTASI DAN MANAJEMEN RESIKO (S2)
   * MANAJEMEN STRATEGI
   * KOMPUTER LEMBAGA KEUANGAN PERBANKAN
   * TEORI EKONOMI MAKRO
   * EKONOMI PEMBANGUNAN
   * PEREKONOMIAN INDONESIA
   * SOSIOLOGI DAN POLITIK
   * KEWARGANEGARAAN
   * RISET AKUNTANSI
   * MANAJEMEN KEUANGAN 02
   * AKUNTANSI MANAJEMEN LANJUTAN
   * SISTEM PENGENDALIAN MANAJEMEN
   * STATISTIK BISNIS
 * SIMPOSIUM NASIONAL AKUNTANSI
   * SNA 18
   * SNA 20
   * TAX EVASION
   * SNA 19
 * Pustaka Keuangan
   * POLITIK EKONOMI KETAHANAN PANGAN INDONESIA
   * Skeptisme Profesional Auditor
 * KOLEKSI EBOOK
 * Jurnalku
 * 





NAMOURA ARABIKA SIDIKALANG BUBUK

September 20, 2020 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment

𝐍𝐀𝐌𝐎𝐔𝐑𝐀 𝐂𝐎𝐅𝐅𝐄𝐄

Mengenal beragam jenis kopi yang sudah mendapat predikat sebagai kopi terbaik
tentu tak lepas dari jenis kopi satu ini, kopi Sidikalang. Jenis kopi satu ini
ternyata tidak kalah populer dengan jenis kopi yang lain seperti kopi Luwak.
Sama sama berasal dari Indonesia, kopi Sidikalang ternyata juga mendapat
pengakuan dari banyak pencinta kopi tidak hanya di Indonesia tapi  juga di
negara negara lain seperti negara Amerika Serikat. Pertanyaannya, lalu apa yang
menjadikan kopi Sidikalang ini begitu spesial?

Kopi Sidikalang ini juga sangat terkenal akan cita rasanya yang unik dan lezat.
Kopi Sidikalang berasal dari Sumatera, tepatnya di sebuah ibukota kabupaten
Dairi, Sumatera Utara.

Selain mendapat pengakuan dari para penikmat kopi di negeri sendiri, negeri
Indonesia, kopi Sidikalang ternyata mampu bersaing dengan jenis kopi lain
termasuk kopi Brazil. Hal ini tentunya bukan sesuatu yang mengejutkan karena
kopi Sidikalang memiliki cita rasa khas yang tidak dimiliki oleh jenis kopi
lain. Di tempat asalnya sendiri, pulau Sumatera, boleh dibilang kopi Sidikalang
adalah rajanya kopi.

 * N𝐀𝐌𝐎𝐔𝐑𝐀 𝐂𝐎𝐅𝐅𝐄𝐄
 * Sidikalang Arabika Bubuk
 * Robusta Sidikalang Bubuk
 * Sidikalang Arabika Roasted Bean

Namoura Coffee dengan bangga menghadirkan ikon kopi sumatera ini untuk kalian
para penikmat kopi berkualitas, Arabika Sidikalang Bubuk yang memiliki kadar
kafein lebih tinggi dibanding jenis kopi lain pada umumnya, aroma khasnya adalah
manis karamel yang berpadu dengan sedikit rasa rempah. Kemudian, after taste
khasnya adalah perpaduan antara citrus, dark chocolate dan fruity yang cukup
segar. Ikon kopi Sumatera ini kami hadirkan dalam bentuk tiga kemasan, yakni:
250 gram, 500 gram, dan 1 Kg.







Categories: Kopi Nusantara, Namoura Coffee, Namourapedia Tags: Arabica, Coffee,
Ground Coffee, Indonesian Coffee, Roasted Bean, Sumatera Coffee


NAMOURA GAYO ARABICS

December 5, 2019 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


Coffee from Takengon, Center of Aceh or commonly called Aceh Gayo coffee is
already famous in the world. As the name implies, this coffee is managed by the
Gayo people who are original Aceh residents. This type of coffee is one of the
most widely consumed coffees as well as exported abroad. Premium product
quality, with professional quality control, Quality control by machine and
manual sorting process (Double Picked).

Specifications:

 * Single Origin Aceh Gayo Arabica Coffee with Grade 1 quality
 * Processing Method: Semi-washed
 * Altitude: +/- 1,400m
 * 11-13% Moisture; Defect 0-3%
 * Quality guaranteed
 * Suitable for roasters and also coffee connoisseurs who like to roast by
   themselves

Come join us here with our Namoura Gayo Arabics.


Categories: Namoura Coffee Tags: Coffee, Ground Coffee, Indonesian Coffee,
Roasted Bean, Sumatera Coffee


THE SEPARATION OF THE ‘ECONOMIC’ AND THE ‘POLITICAL’ UNDER CAPITALISM:
‘CAPITAL-CENTRIC MARXISM’ AND THE CAPITALIST STATE

March 24, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment

‘The Iron Rolling Mill’ by Adolf Menzel

One of the central claims of Capital-centric Marxism is that capitalism is the
first mode of production in human history whose social property relations are
reproduced through market competition. Capitalism’s unique laws of motion/rules
of reproduction—the law of value which compels producers to economize labor-time
through productive specialization, labor-saving technical innovation and the
accumulation of surplus-value—operates through the mechanism of price
competition. Put simply, capitalism is reproduced through the “dull compulsion
of the market place” rather than through varied forms of extra-economic
coercion.

The capitalist state, from this perspective, is distinguished from all previous
forms of political domination by its relative separation from the capitalist
economy. The capitalist state constitutes what Heidi Gerstenberger has called
a public sphere of “impersonal power;” while exploitation is privatized in
individual units of production. In the words of Ellen Meiksins Wood in her
seminal essay “The Separation of the ‘Economic’ and the ‘Political’ in
Capitalism”:

To speak of the differentiation of the economic sphere…is not, of course, to
suggest that the political dimension is somehow extraneous to capitalist
relations of production. The political sphere in capitalism has a special
character because the coercive power supporting capitalist exploitation is not
wielded directly by the appropriator and is not based on the producer’s
political or juridical subordination to an appropriating master. But a coercive
power and a structure of domination remain essential… Absolute private property,
the contractual relation that binds producer to appropriator, the process of
commodity exchange—all these require legal forms, the coercive apparatus, the
policing functions of the state.2

While the capitalist state provides the ‘general conditions of accumulation,’ it
does not direct the distribution of labor-power and means of production within
and between branches of production. Instead, it is the law of value operating
through real market competition that insures the reproduction of this mode of
production. The unique dynamism of capitalism—the constant development of the
productive forces—and its crisis tendencies—falling profits as a result of the
increasing mechanization of production—operate independently of the desires and
goals of either individual capitalists or its “Executive Committee,” the
capitalist state. Again, as Wood argued:

… the social functions of production and distribution, surplus extraction and
appropriation, and the allocation of social labor are, so to speak, privatized
and they are achieved by non-authoritative, non-political means. In other words,
the social allocation of resources and labor does not, on the whole, take place
by means of political direction, communal deliberation, heredity duty, custom,
or religious obligation, but rather through the mechanisms of commodity
exchange.3

Many critics of “Political Marxism” have labelled this approach a “Hayekian
Marxism” that limits the “general conditions of production” to the provisions of
certain infrastructure that individual capitalists cannot produce profitably.
This perspective, it is argued, cannot account for the key features of
the concrete history of capitalism. Specifically, Capital-centric Marxism cannot
explain the role of the capitalist state in creating capitalist social property
relations, the persistence of legally coerced labor under capitalism; or the
growth of capitalist state economic intervention in the twentieth and
twenty-first centuries. In this essay, we will attempt to sketch the barest
outline of a Capital-centric account of the roots and limits of capitalist state
policies that attempt to shape social relations and the course of accumulation.
In this task, I draw not only on Marx’s Capital—the most important of Marx’s
mature, scientific works—but on a variety of works in or close to the tradition
of “Political Marxism.”

Michael Zmolek’s excellent new book, Rethinking the Industrial Revolution4,
directly addresses, from an explicitly Capital-centric perspective, the role of
the capitalist state in the creation and consolidation of capitalist social
property relations in England. Brenner, Wood and others have been quite
insistent that the operation of capitalist rules of reproduction—specialization,
innovation and accumulation—cannot explain the origins of capitalist social
property relations. Put simply, the process of ‘primitive accumulation’—the
establishment of capitalist social relations of production—is not the result of
the spread of markets or the development of the productive forces. Instead, it
is the unintended consequences of attempts of pre-capitalist classes to
reproduce themselves in periods of crisis that produce capitalism. In this
process, the state plays a crucial role. Zmolek’s discussions of enclosures and
the expropriation and sale of monastery lands in Tudor England give new
historical depth and sophistication to Marx’s discussions in the section on
“primitive accumulation” in Capital.

Zmolek’s discussion of the role of the post-1688 British capitalist state in the
creation of an industrial working class is especially important. Marx was quite
clear that the ‘dull compulsion’ of the market was not sufficient to discipline
propertyless wage workers when capital had not yet conquered the labor-process.
As long as capital’s subsumption of labor was formal and the actual
labor-process was in the hands of skilled artisanal wage earners—legal-juridical
forces was necessary to ensure the sale of labor-power and capital’s ability to
command production. The majority of workers can be “dually free”—free from
possession of objects and instruments of production; and free of non-market
legal-juridical compulsion to labor—only when capital has achieved real
subsumption of labor. Only when capitalists both face a mass of workers without
non-market access to the means of production and are able to constantly
reproduce a reserve army of labor through the mechanization of production, can
capital effectively secure an adequate and reliable supply of labor power
without legal and juridical restrictions on workers. Zmolek’s discussion of the
central role of the British capitalist state in destroying artisanal wage
workers’ resistance to the real subsumption of labor to capital again
concretizes these insights.



Legally coerced wage labor also persists in capitalist agriculture, where the
disjuncture between production and labor time5 makes non-market coercion
necessary to secure adequate supplies of labor power during crucial periods like
planting and harvesting. Legally coerced wage labor is also found in situations
where capital has command of industrial labor-processes, but where workers are
only partially separated from landed property. For example, in apartheid South
Africa, workers were not “free” to enter or leave labor contracts at will.6 The
specific forms of capitalist social property relations that emerged in the South
African countryside and urban centers after the 1913 Natives’ Land
Act—the partial separation of the African population from the means of
production—necessitated this legal coercion. Africans were able to partially
reproduce their labor-power outside of the wage-relation either in the “Reserve
Areas” or on plots of land provided by capitalist farmers. This “partial
proletarianization” required the “pass laws” that legally restricted geographic
mobility of labor-power in order to ensure steady supplies of ‘cheap’ African
labor power to capital.

Today, millions of non-market coerced wage workers—often mislabeled ‘slaves’—are
compelled to sell their labor-power often for less than the cost of their
reproduction, and are prevented from leaving employers to seek better wages and
conditions. As David McNally and Susan Ferguson7 have argued, most of these
workers are migratory workers who do not enjoy the legal rights/freedom of
citizens. The extra-economic coercion they face is crucial to supplying
inexpensive labor-power to labor-intensive sectors—sex-work, domestic servants,
landscape workers, hotel cleaners, janitors, home construction, garment
production, and certain branches of agriculture. Real capitalist accumulation
and competition compels capitalists in labor-intensive industries to pay low
wages—wages often below the costs of reproduction—in order to earn the average
rate of profit.8 Legal coercion in the form of the denial of civil and political
rights is often required to provide such “cheap” labor-power.

The reality of capitalist competition through the “artillery of fixed capital”
also explain the role of the capitalist state historically in attempting to
protect “infant” capitalist industries. Anwar Shaikh, in his seminal essay
“Foreign Trade and the Law of Value,”9 has argued out those capitalist classes
that entered the world market after the consolidation of industrial capitalism
in Britain were faced with a dilemma. Whether in Germany, Italy, Japan or the US
in the nineteenth century, or in the global South in the twenty and twenty-first
centuries, “late industrializers” found they were unable to compete directly
with the older, more capital-intensive producers. “Free trade” meant remaining
exporters of agricultural goods, raw materials and low-end, labor-intensive
manufactured goods. Only those ruling classes that succeeded in establishing
protective tariffs and selective state subsidies for capital-intensive export
industries succeeded in carving out a place for themselves in the capitalist
world economy. As Vivek Chibber points out in Locked in Place: State-Building
and Late Industrialization in India10, protective tariffs as part of “import
substitution industrialization” programs were insufficient, allowing inefficient
manufacturing in many parts of the global south to survive for decades. However,
“export led industrialization” programs had a very different impact. When
capitalist classes were ready and willing to compete globally, usually in social
formations where the capitalist transformation of agriculture had created a
competitive home market, forms of capitalist state intervention and protection
were necessary preconditions for successful industrialization.

Finally, Joaquim Hirsch’s essay “The State Apparatus and Social Reproduction:
Elements of a Theory of the Capitalist State”11 provides important insights into
the roots and limits of capitalist state intervention in the advanced capitalist
countries in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries. The state-derivation
school, of which Hirsch was a prominent figure, shared with “Political Marxism”
the goal of providing a Marxist analysis of the form of the capitalist state—of
a “public power” separate from the private sphere of exploitation and
accumulation. Like Wood, Hirsch rooted the separation of the political and
economic in the specific social property relations and rules of reproduction of
capitalism. The “state derivation” school also sought to counter various
neo-Keynesian and neo-reformist arguments that capitalist state fiscal and
monetary policy, combined with forms of ‘indicative planning’ and limited
nationalizations, had finally created a crisis-free form of ‘managed’ or ‘state
monopoly capital.’ Put another way, Hirsch’s arguments point to how the
separation of the political and economic that characterizes capitalism
essentially limits the capacity of capitalist state personnel to alter the rules
of reproduction of capitalism through the construction of institutional
frameworks—the Regulationists’ “regimes of accumulation”—to regulate the
economy. Instead, it is the dynamics of accumulation, competition and
profitability that place strict limits on the actions of capitalist state
personnel, as we have seen time and again in the past forty years beginning with
the Mitterand regime in France in the early 1980s through, most recently, the
capitulation of Syrizia in Greece to the austerity agenda of the European Union.

Starting from an account of the separation of the political and economic that is
essentially the same as that of Capital-centric Marxists, Hirsch concludes: 

… that the bourgeois state, by reason of its essential character [its formal
separation from the economy—CP], cannot act as regulator of the social process
of development, but must be understood in the determination of its concrete
functions as a reaction to the fundamentally crisis-ridden course of the
economic and social process of reproduction. The developing state
interventionism represents a form in which the contradictions of capital can
temporarily move; but the movement of capital remains historically determining…
These can be condensed in terms of value theory in the law of the tendency of
the rate of profit to fall, which also means that this law must be the
conceptual point of departure for an analysis of state functions, to be
developed out of the concrete course of capital accumulation and class
conflict.12

Put simply, other than the extension of political rights to workers and the
expansion of the welfare state which were temporary concessions to working class
struggle that never undermined labor-market discipline, the logic of capitalist
state economic policy is driven by attempts to mobilize the counter-tendencies
to the falling rate of profit.13Whether the use of fiscal and monetary policy to
stimulate demand, manipulate interest rates or provide tax subsidies to various
capitals; incomes policies and restrictions on trade union rights; or the
mechanisms of indicative planning and nationalization (usually of less
productive capitals), capitalist state economic policies aim facilitate
increasing the rate of surplus-value and destroying redundant capitals—without
the collapse of accumulation that comes with crises.

The abandonment of Keynesian policies in the late 1970s and early 1980s
reflected the limits of capitalist state policy and the necessity of periodic
capitalist crises.14 Despite the massive expansion of ‘state intervention,’
capitalist state policies operated at a distance from accumulation and could not
prevent a new crisis of profitability. The shift to neo-liberalism facilitated
the revival of profitability and accumulation between 1982 and 2007 because it
was effective in facilitating the increased exploitation of labor and the
destruction of inefficient firms. However, neo-liberalism—like all other
capitalist state policies—could not prevent a renewed crisis of profitability
beginning in 2008. These crises are rooted in the operation capitalism’s most
fundamental laws of motion/rules of reproduction—the operation of the law of
value through specialization, innovation and accumulation under the whip of
market competition—which are beyond the ability of capitalist state managers to
effectively regulate.



Ultimately, the Capital-centric understanding of the place of the capitalist
state in the ensemble of capitalist social property relations points to the need
to radically disrupt the separation of the political and economic in order to
transcend capitalism. Because capitalist state policies are ultimately limited
by independent dynamics of profitability, the capitalist state institutions
cannot be utilized in some instrumental fashion to abolish capitalism in some
piece-meal manner, as strategies of “non-reformist reforms” argue. Instead,
working people will have to confront the capitalist state and build their own
organs of political and social power—which will abolish the separation of the
political and economic—in order to build a new, democratic socialist order.


———————-

1 “The Bourgeois State Form Revisted,” in W. Bonefeld, et al. (eds.) Open
Marxism, Volume I: Dialectics and History (London: Pluto Press,
1992); Impersonal Power: History and Theory of the Bourgeois State, (Chicago:
Haymarket Books, 2009)

2 “The Separation of the ‘Economic’ and the ‘Political’ in Capitalism,”
in Democracy Against Capitalism: Renewing Historical Materialism (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 29-30.

4Rethinking the Industrial Revolution: Five Centuries of Transition from
Agrarian to Industrial Capitalism in England (Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2014).

5 Susan Archer Mann, Agrarian Capitalism in Theory and Practice (Chapel Hill,
NC: University of North Carolina Press, 1990), Chapter Two.

6 This argument is detailed in Martin J. Murray and Charles Post, “The ‘Agrarian
Question,’ Class Struggle and the Capitalist State in South Africa and the
United States,” Insurgent Sociologist, Volume 11, Number 3 (Winter 1984).

7 “Precarious Migrants: Gender, Race and the Social Reproduction of a Global
Working Class,” in L. Panitch and G. Albo (eds.), Socialist Register 2015:
Transforming Classes (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2014).

8 Howard Botwinick, Persistent Inequalities: Wage Disparities under Capitalist
Competition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.

10 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003). See also “Development from
Below,” Jacobin 19 (2015)
[https://www.jacobinmag.com/2015/11/development-state-korea-india-nehru-postcolonial-global-south-chibber/]

11 In J. Holloway and S. Picciotto (eds.), State and Capital: A Marxist
Debate (Austin, TX: University of Texas Press, 1978)

13 For a similar argument see G. McCormack and T. Workman, The Servant State:
Overseeing Capital Accumulation in Canada (Blackwood, NS: Fernwood Press, 2015)

14 See David McNally, Global Slump: The Economics and Politics of Crisis and
Resistance (Oakland, CA, PM Press, 2011) and Anwar Shaikh, “The First Great
Depression of the 21st Century” in L. Panitch, G. Albo and V. Chibber
(eds.), Socialist Register 2011: The Crisis This Time (New York: Monthly Review
Press, 2010).

Source:


Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: capital,
capitalism, capitalist, Economics, Political Economy, Politics, Politics
Philosophy


CAN DEMOCRACY REDUCE INEQUALITY

March 23, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


Despite two decades of social policies targeting poverty and inequality, Latin
America remains one of the most economically unequal regions in the world.
Recurrent protests motivated by economic grievances have been a regular reminder
of this reality. The ongoing health crisis caused by the coronavirus pandemic
has disproportionately harmed already vulnerable populations, undoing some of
the progress made. At the same time, democracy has taken root in the region, and
participation in elections is growing. Then why hasn’t democracy been more
effective in resolving Latin America’s persistent inequality?

Research shows voters are not able to make their demands for greater
redistribution heard, while governments are not implementing redistributive
policies at the desired pace. Reasons include unequal political participation,
institutional bias against redistribution, and vote buying. Until such
impediments are removed, democracy’s impact on inequality will remain limited.

Between 2000 and 2018, income inequality in Latin America, as measured by
the Gini index, gradually fell from 53.3 to 45.7. During the same period,
government spending on social protection steadily increased by almost one
percentage point of GDP. While these trends seem promising, inequality in Latin
America remains high and social spending low by the standards of more advanced
economies. For example, the thirty-six countries of the OECD reported a Gini
index of only 33.2 in 2018. That is puzzling, given that at least on paper,
Latin America is built on similar economic and political principles—market
economies and representative democracies. One would expect that the democratic
process, which by design is based on the egalitarian principle of “one person,
one vote”, would lead to policies that reduce market inequalities. In other
words, in a well-functioning democracy, inequality should to some extent be
self-correcting. Why isn’t this happening to a greater degree in Latin America?


WEAK VOTER DEMAND FOR POLICIES THAT LOWER INEQUALITY

A first explanation is that voter demand for inequality-reducing policies
remains relatively weak. Lack of voter pressure can be seen in limited and
unequal political participation. Despite the widespread use of compulsory
voting, voter turnout in the region has remained below 70% on average. More
importantly, turnout is biased in a way that is detrimental to the poor, as
voting is less common among the less educated and the less wealthy.

Even when they do vote, the less well-off are less informed, and thus less
effective in choosing candidates that represent their economic interests. The
poor are the greatest beneficiaries of basic public services, such as public
education and health care. Unfortunately, voter demand for government
investments in these public goods is tenuous, either due to low trust in the
ability of public officials to spend public resources in these areas
effectively, or due to a preference for immediate benefits such as cash
transfers, at the expense of longer-term benefits such as high-quality education
and public safety.


WEAK SUPPLY OF POLICIES DESIGNED TO REDUCE INEQUALITY

A second explanation is that the policymaking process may fail to internalize
popular demand for redistribution. In some cases, this occurs because political
institutions can be manipulated by incumbents to retain power, for example
through legislative malapportionment. Others argue that elements of the elite
gain access to and remain in power using campaign donations from narrow interest
groups, obviating the need to rely on broad popular support.

More recent research has shown that vote buying by political candidates, a
prevalent phenomenon in many Latin American democracies, subverts the normal
functioning of the budget process. Voters targeted with vote buying prior to an
election may receive no government benefits after the election. As poorer voters
are more susceptible to vote buying, they are often left unrepresented in the
subsequent negotiations over the budget. Thus, vote buying crowds out
redistributive spending that could reduce inequality.


STRONGER DEMOCRACIES BETTER ALLEVIATE INEQUALITY

In a chapter of the recent IDB report entitled The Inequality Crisis I present
new data patterns that support the idea that the strength of democracy matters
for the alleviation of inequality. I use the Economist Intelligence Unit
democracy index to rank democratic quality along five dimensions. Among Latin
American countries, stronger democracies provide more redistributive spending.
At one end of the spectrum, Nicaragua spends less than 1% of GDP on social
protection, compared to almost 7% in Uruguay, at the other end of the spectrum.
Interestingly, stronger democracies are also characterized by higher voter
turnout and fewer protests. This suggests that voting, rather than protesting,
is a catalyst for government redistribution. Protests appear to be a symptom of
unmet economic expectations.

Some development institutions, such as the UNDP, have suggested that inequality
may be one of democracy’s greatest weaknesses. As the less well-off are
economically marginalized, they become more disengaged with the democratic
process. However, a weaker democracy may also fail to alleviate inequality.
Overcoming this vicious circle remains a challenge for Latin America’s young
democracies. Political and civic leaders in the region should renew their
commitment to strengthening democratic institutions, chief among them free
elections, civic liberties, and independent media. Over time, better-functioning
democracies should improve economic equity. Democracy can certainly reduce
inequality, as long as it functions as intended.

Source:




Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: Democracy,
Economics, Inequality, Political Economy, Politics


THE WAGE CURVE ACROSS THE WEALTH DISTRIBUTION

March 22, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


The uneven distribution of wealth in society is commonly perceived as a matter
of concern per se for inequality-averse policymakers. However, being wealth-poor
or wealth-rich is also correlated with outcomes in the labour market. This
column examines how wages and unemployment vary across the relative distribution
of personal wealth in Norway, focusing on the wage-to-unemployment ratio across
the different percentiles of the wealth distribution. It finds that wealth-poor
individuals cannot escape low labour incomes regardless of the unemployment rate
they face, while the unemployment elasticity of wages is substantially higher
for wealth-rich individuals.

Economists have long come to accept inequality in the pace of wealth
accumulation across the wealth distribution as a more accurate measure of
inequality than income (Mankiw 2015).

However, the academic debate has in recent years focused on documenting the
extent to which both capital income and wealth are concentrated in the hands of
a few individuals (Piketty 2014, see also König et al. (2020) for a recent
survey).

Stiglitz (2015) highlights the need to document the changing distribution of
income and wealth, but also calls for new complementary facts to be studied. In
their Vox column, Kanbur and Stiglitz (2015) conclude: “We need to focus on the
interaction between income from physical and financial capital and income from
human capital in determining snapshot inequality”.

Along these same lines, our research highlights the extent to which the
distribution of wealth holdings is unambiguously associated with outcomes in the
labour market (Iacono and Ranaldi 2020). We argue that the relative distribution
of personal wealth is relevant not only per se but also to better comprehend the
role of wealth in shaping individuals’ working trajectories over the life cycle.


PERSONAL WEALTH AND THE LABOUR MARKET

The empirical relationship between gross wages and the unemployment rate (the
so-called wage curve) is a matter of great relevance to policymakers and has
been studied extensively by economists. Do wages respond to changes in the
unemployment rate, for instance? I.e. do wages adjust if there is an unexpected
surge in unemployment, as in the current pandemic? Does the unemployment rate
vary when wages rise? This wage curve has been estimated previously across
space, both at the national (Blanchflower and Oswald 1994) and regional levels
(Blanchflower and Oswald 1995). In our paper, we estimate the wage curve through
the lens of the personal wealth distribution. Ranking individuals according to
their wealth holdings allows us to uncover several stylized facts related to
labour market outcomes that are associated with wealth, rather than with
traditional explanatory variables such as educational attainment or parental
background. Thanks to the rich and fine-grained administrative data on personal
wealth in Norway, our sample covers the entire population of residents between
2000 and 2015. Based on this large-scale sample, we document several novel facts
about the wage curve across the wealth distribution.

The first stylised fact shows that the elasticity of the wage curve – how gross
wages change with a change in the unemployment rate – increases monotonically
with gross wealth, as shown in Figure 1.

Figure 1 The wage curve across the wealth distribution

This figure shows that wealth-poor individuals cannot escape low labour
incomes regardless of the unemployment rate they face (a sort of double poverty
trap in the sense of low income and low wealth), while variation in unemployment
is much lower for wealth-rich individuals. The latter enjoy a higher range of
wage incomes, regardless of the unemployment rate they face. Note that we always
compare individuals in the same percentiles of the wealth distribution in our
analysis.



Second, we highlight that the distribution of unemployment across the wealth
ladder is highly uneven when comparing the bottom with the top of the wealth
distribution. In fact, we construct the first distribution of unemployed
individuals across the wealth ladder between 2000 and 2015 in Norway and show
that the share of unemployed individuals in the bottom 10% of the wealth
distribution is ten times larger than the share in the top 10% of the
distribution in Norway (compare Figure 2).

Figure 2 Share of unemployed by gross wealth decile

In our view, the unemployment share at the bottom of the wealth distribution can
be considered a measure of the vulnerability of the unemployed. Assume that two
countries have the same overall unemployment rate but a different share of
unemployed at the bottom of the wealth distribution; then, an economic shock
might be more harmful to the country with a higher share of unemployed at the
bottom of the distribution. In fact, if an economic shock, such as a financial
crisis or a pandemic, should suddenly occur, the ability to economically
overcome that shock is a positive function of the wealth held by the unemployed.

We also analyze how the relationship between wages and unemployment changes when
individuals move along the wealth ladder. To answer this question precisely, one
would ideally need to follow the same individuals across the life cycle to
disentangle the effect of switching from one decile of the wealth distribution
to another. Alternatively, we provide a first step in this direction by
estimating the relationship between wealth deciles (our preferred measure of
wealth status) and the wage-to-unemployment ratio, summarizing the principal
labour market characteristics. Whenever the wage-to-unemployment ratio is low,
we have a labour market with rather stagnant wages and sustained rates of
unemployment. In contrast, a high wage-to-unemployment ratio is associated with
high wages and rather low unemployment rates. Figure 3 confirms the findings
presented in Figure 1 of this column, showing that the wage-to-unemployment
ratio (vertical axis) increases across wealth deciles (horizontal axis),
indicating that belonging to higher deciles of the wealth distribution is
associated with better wages and lower unemployment.

Figure 3 The wage-to-unemployment ratio across gross wealth deciles

All in all, these findings show the extent to which wealth inequality shapes
labour market outcomes. This further motivates the need to better design wealth
redistribution policies. In addition, the stylized fact that wealth-poor
individuals are trapped in a state of low income regardless of the unemployment
rate does not easily follow from standard competitive labour market modelling.
Hence, we advocate for more evidence on the matter, not only to inform public
policies aimed at improving employment opportunities but also to improve the
macroeconomic modelling of the labour market. Moreover, we think that our main
result, whereby the slope of the wage curve is a positive function of gross
wealth, can be incorporated in any macroeconomic model of the labour market that
wishes to account for wealth inequality in its dynamics.


CONCLUDING REMARKS

The new stylized facts of our column on wealth and its role in the labour market
can be summarised as follows:

 * The distribution of unemployed people across the wealth ladder in Norway is
   highly uneven.
 * The negative slope of the wage curve, previously estimated in the national or
   regional space, is also confirmed within the (distributive) wealth space.
 * The wage-to-unemployment ratio increases monotonically with increasing gross
   wealth.
 * Wealth-poor unemployed individuals are substantially more vulnerable to
   economic shocks than wealth-rich individuals since the former also receive
   lower wages in the labour market.


REFERENCES 

Blanchflower, D G and A J Oswald (1994), “Estimating a Wage Curve for Britain
1973-90”, The Economic Journal 104 (426): 1025–1043. 



Blanchflower, D G and A J Oswald (1995), “An introduction to the wage
curve”, Journal of Economic Perspectives 9(3): 153-167.

Iacono, R and M Ranaldi (2020), “The Wage Curve across the Wealth
Distribution”, Economics Letters 196, 109580.

Kanbur, R and J Stiglitz (2015), “Wealth and income distribution: New theories
needed for a new era”, VoxEU.org, 18 August. 

König, J, C Schröder and E N Wolff (2020), „Wealth Inequalities“, In:
Zimmermann, K F (eds) Handbook of Labor, Human Resources and Population
Economics, Springer. 

Mankiw, N G (2015), “Yes, r > g. So What?”, American Economic Review 105 (5):
43-47.

Piketty, T (2014), Capital in the XXIst Century, Harvard University Press. 

Stiglitz, J E (2015), “New Theoretical Perspectives on the Distribution of
Income and Wealth Among Individuals: Parts I-IV”, NBER Working Papers
21189-21192.

Source:


Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: Economics,
Inequality, Wealth Distribution


CAPITALIST SYSTEMS AND INCOME INEQUALITY

March 21, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


Similar levels of income inequality may coexist with completely different
distributions of capital and labor incomes. This column introduces a new measure
of compositional inequality, allowing the authors to distinguish between
different capitalist societies. The analysis suggests that Latin America and
India are rigid ‘class-based’ societies, whereas in most of Western European and
North American economies (as well as in Japan and China), the split between
capitalists and workers is less sharp and inequality is moderate or low. Nordic
countries are ‘class-based’ yet fairly equal. Taiwan and Slovakia are closest to
classless and low inequality societies. 

Similar levels of income inequality may be characterised by completely different
distributions of capital and labour. People who belonged to the highest income
decile in the US before WWII received mainly capital incomes, whereas in 2010
people in the highest decile earned both high labour and capital incomes
(Piketty 2014). Yet the difference in their total income shares was small.   

Different distributions of capital and labour describe different economic
systems. Two polar systems are particularly relevant. In classical capitalism –
explicit in the writings of Ricardo (1994 [1817]) and Marx (1992 [1867], 1993
[1885]) ¬– a group of people receives incomes entirely from ownership of assets
while another group’s income derives entirely from labour. The first group
(capitalists) is generally small and rich; the latter (workers) is generally
numerous and poor, or at best with middling income levels. The system is
characterised by high income inequality. 

In today’s liberal capitalism, however, a significant percentage of people
receive incomes from both capital and labour (Milanovic 2019). It is still true
that the share of one’s income derived from capital increases as we move higher
in the income distribution, but very often the rich have both high capital and
high labour incomes. While inter-personal income inequality may still be high,
inequality in composition of income is much less. 

The purpose of our study is to introduce a new way of looking at inequality that
allows us to classify empirically different forms of capitalism. In addition to
the usual inter-personal income inequality, we look at inequality in the
factoral (capital or labour) composition of people’s incomes. The class analysis
(where class is defined narrowly depending on the type of income one receives)
is thus separated from the analysis of income inequality proper.    

Which countries around the world are closer to classical, and which to liberal
capitalism? Does classical capitalism display higher inter-personal income
inequality than liberal capitalism? Can we find what we term ‘homoploutic’
societies – where everyone has approximately the same shares of capital and
labour income? Would such homoploutic societies display high or low levels of
income inequality?   

To answer these questions, in Ranaldi and Milanovic (2020) we adopt a new
statistic, recently developed by Ranaldi (2020), to estimate compositional
inequality of incomes: the income-factor concentration (IFC) index. The
income-factor concentration index is at the maximum when individuals at the top
and at the bottom of the total income distribution earn two different types of
income, and minimal when each individual has the same shares of capital and
labour income. When the income-factor concentration index is close to one
(maximal value), compositional inequality is high, and a society can be
associated to classical capitalism. When the index is close to zero,
compositional inequality is low and a society can be seen as homoploutic
capitalism. Liberal capitalism would lie in-between. Negative values of the
income-factor concentration index, which describe societies with poor
capitalists and rich workers, are unlikely to be found in practice.

By applying this methodology to 47 countries with micro data provided by
Luxembourg Income Study from Europe, North America, Oceania, Asia, and Latin
America in the last 25 years and covering approximately the 80% of world output,
three main empirical findings emerge.   

First, classical capitalism tends to be associated with higher income inequality
than liberal capitalism (see Figure 1). Although this relationship was implicit
in the minds of classical authors like Ricardo and Marx, as well as in recent
studies of pre-WWI inequality in countries that are thought to have had strong
class divisions (Bartels et al. 2020, Gómes Léon and de Jong 2018), it was never
tested empirically.

Note: The graph shows on the horizontal axis compositional inequality and on the
vertical axis the standard measure of inter-personal income inequality (Gini
coefficient). Nordic countries (Finland, Sweden, Norway and Denmark) are marked
in red.



Second, three major clusters emerge at the global scale. The first cluster is
the one of advanced economies, which includes Western Europe, North America, and
Oceania. Relatively low to moderate levels of both income and compositional
inequality characterize this cluster. The US and Israel stand somewhat apart
from the core countries since they display higher inequality in both
dimensions. 

Latin American countries represent the second cluster, and are, on average,
characterised by high levels in both inequality dimensions. 

The third cluster is composed of Nordic countries and is exceptional insofar as
it combines low levels of income inequality with high compositional inequality.
This is not entirely surprising: Nordic countries are known to combine wage
compressions with ‘socially acceptable’ high returns to capital (Moene and
Wallerstein 2003, Moene 2016). Such compromise between capital and labour
(reached in the early 1930s) has put a cap on earning inequality within the
region (Fochesato and Bowles 2015) but has left wealth inequality untouched
(Davies et al. 2012). By drastically reducing the progressivity of capital
income taxation (Iacono and Palagi 2020), income tax reforms during the 1990s
have worked in the same direction.

Several other results are found. Many Eastern European countries are close to
the Nordic cluster. Some (Lithuania and Romania) have very high compositional
inequality, likely the product of concentrated privatisation of state assets.
India is very similar to the Latin American cluster, displaying a class-based
structure with high levels of income inequality.

Taiwan and Slovakia are, instead, the most ‘classless’ societies of all. They
combine very low levels of income and compositional inequality. This makes them
‘inequality-resistant’ to the increase in the capital share of income. In other
words, if capital share continues to rise due to further automation and robotics
(Baldwin 2019, Marin 2014), it will not push inter-personal inequality
up:  everybody’s income would increase by the same percentage. The link between
the functional and personal income distribution in such societies is weak – the
topic of a previous VoxEU column by Milanovic (2017b). It is also interesting
that Taiwan is both more ‘classless’ and less unequal than China.

The third, and perhaps most striking result that emerges from our analysis is
that no one country in our sample occupies the north-west part of the diagram.
We find no evidence of countries combining low levels of compositional
inequality (like those of Taiwan and Slovakia) with extremely high levels of
income inequality (like in Latin America). 

To conclude, we propose a novel taxonomy of varieties of capitalism on the basis
of the two inequality dimensions (Table 1). We believe such taxonomy brings a
strong empirical and distributional focus into the literature on the varieties
of capitalism, as well as a larger geographical coverage.

Table 1. Nomenclature of capitalism


REFERENCES

Baldwin, R (2019), The Globotics Upheaval: Globalization, Robotics and the
Future of Work, Princeton University Press.

Bartels, C, F Kersting and N Wolf (2020), “Testing Marx: Inequality,
Concentration and Political Polarization in late 19th Century Germany”, German
Institute for Economic Research.

Davies, J, R Lluberas and A Shorrocks (2012), Credit Suisse Global Wealth Report
2012.

Fochesato, M and S Bowles (2015), “Nordic exceptionalism? Social democratic
egalitarianism in world-historic perspective”, Journal of Public Economics 127:
30-44.

Gómes Léon, M and H J de Jong (2018), “Inequality in turbulent times: income
distribution in Germany and Britain, 1900–50”, Economic History Review. 

Iacono, R and E Palagi (2020), “Still the Lands of Equality? On the
Heterogeneity of Individual Factor Income Shares in the Nordics”, LIS working
papers series 791.

Marin, D (2014), “Globalization and the Rise of the Robots”, Vox.EU.org, 15
November.

Marx, K (1992 [1867]), Capital: A Critique of Political Economy 1, translated by
B Fowkes, London: Penguin Classics. 

Marx, K (1993 [1885]), Capital: A Critique of Political Economy 3, translated by
D Fernbach, London: Penguin Classics.

Milanovic, B (2017a), “Increasing Capital Income Share and its Effect on
Personal Income Inequality”, in H Boushey, J Bradford DeLong and M Steinbaum
(eds) After Piketty. The Agenda for Economics and Inequality. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press. 



Milanovic, B (2017b), “Rising Capital Share and Transmission Into Higher
Interpersonal Inequality”, Vox.EU.org, 16 May. 

Milanovic, B (2019), Capitalism, Alone, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

Moene, K O and M Wallerstein (2003), “Social democracy as a development
strategy”, Department of Economics, University of Oslo 35/2003.

Moene, K O (2016), “The Social Upper Class under Social Democracy”, Nordic
Economic Policy Review 2: 245–261.

Ricardo, D (2004 [1817]), The Principles of Political Economy and
Taxation, London: Dover publications.  

Ranaldi, M (2020), “Income Composition Inequality”, Stone Center Working Paper
Series 7.

Ranaldi, M and B Milanovic (2020), “Capitalist Systems and Income Inequality”,
Stone Center Working Paper Series 25.

Piketty, T (2014), Capital in the Twenty-First Century, translate by A
Goldhammer, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Source:


Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: capital,
capitalism, capitalist, economic developments, Economics, Inequality


HOW INEQUALITY UNDERMINES DEMOCRACY?

March 20, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


Inequality has been on the rise over the last three decades, and has been a
pervasive issue in the recent U.S. national election. On one level, income
inequality is a non-issue in a market economy where there will always be winners
and losers. In a market where individuals are free to make choices and reap the
rewards of the choices they make, it is a given that some will wind up with more
than others. We cannot all be equal because we don’t all have the same natural
endowments. Those with certain skills and abilities will often wind up with more
than those without. And those who went to school to train for specific
occupations that pay well will earn more than those who did not. In short,
skilled workers will earn more than non-skilled workers. Consequently, in an
increasingly global economy where there will be two classes —  skilled and
educated workers at the top earning high wages and unskilled and poorly educated
workers at the bottom earning low wages — there is bound to be inequality.
Moreover, as these trends continue, the gap between the top and the bottom is
only bound to grow. On another level, however, income inequality is a seminal
issue because of what it really speaks to: the disappearance of the middle
class. Inequality per se may not be the problem; rather it is the rate of
increase in inequality. In this essay, I argue that to the extent that
inequality effectively speaks to a shrinking middle class it represents a threat
to democracy.

Rising Inequality



Income inequality is an amorphous concept. When we talk about income inequality
we are often talking about the gap between the top and the bottom. The extent to
which it is a problem is contingent on just how it is measured. General income
inequality, as measured by the ratio of the incomes of the top fifth of the
population to those of the bottom fifth, for instance, includes in all income;
not just income earned laboring. For those at the top this can include wages,
interest and dividend income.[i] For those at the bottom this can include income
supports, which are usually subsidies or in-kind assistance that has the effect
of boosting the wages of those at the bottom or their effective purchasing
power. Income at the bottom, then, often includes wages plus these supports,
whether through public assistance transfer programs and/or disability programs.
Therefore, wage income will not be the same as income inequality, and this gap
between the top and bottom will tend to be less.

General income inequality has in recent decades been on the rise. Those at the
top of the distribution have seen their incomes increase while those at the
bottom have seen their incomes decrease in real terms. Prior to 1973, the
incomes of families in the bottom fifth of the income distribution in the U.S.
grew more rapidly than the income of families in other countries. After 1973
low-income families in the U.S. experienced a steady decline in real income,
especially from the late 1970s through the middle of the 1990s. Between 1979 and
2007, the top one percent of families had 60 percent of the income gains while
the bottom 90 percent only had about 9 percent of those income gains (Belman and
Wolfson 2014). Income inequality, especially after 1980, exploded with the top
decile share of the national income rising to between 45-50 percent in the
2000s. This may nonetheless understate the problem, which in recent years has
been couched as the very top pulling away from the rest because a subclass of
“supermanagers” — those at the top of the distribution with great ability and
talent, who in some cases were viewed as “superstars” because they were able to
make their companies profitable and return a high rate of return to shareholders
— emerged who were earning extremely high compensation (Hacker and Pierson 2010;
Piketty 2014).

The Threat to Democracy



Democratic theory assumes a society of free, equal, and autonomous individuals.
Although democracy may have different meanings for different people, an ideal of
democracy is that all individuals are supposed to have equal standing. This
means that each individual is equal before the law, has the same vote as other
individuals, the same right to express oneself in the political sphere, and
perhaps most importantly the same potential to influence what government does,
even if they opt not to exercise that potential. All citizens, then, have the
same access to governing institutions. Within this theoretical construct, which
may also characterize American democracy, money is supposed to be irrelevant to
one’s standing. Both the rich and the poor are equal before government (Hacker
and Pierson 2010). This conception of equality, otherwise known as procedural
equality is not usually concerned with how resources, wealth and income are
distributed, but with how individuals stand in relation to one another.
Individuals can have more than others so long as they are equal in terms of
their legal and political standing. Procedural equality is especially critical
to democratic society because it serves to secure another essential condition:
personal freedom, which is also a necessary condition for individuals to
function autonomously. The greater their autonomy, the more likely they are to
participate in the democratic process. Individuals are free to pursue their
goals and objectives—i.e. self-interests—so long as their pursuit does not
interfere with others’ ability to pursue their own goals and objectives. In a
very basic sense, and certainly within the context of classical political
thought, this is what it means to talk about personal independence or autonomy.
But as Tocqueville observed there cannot be real political equality without some
measure of economic equality as well, because a society with great
concentrations of poor people can be dangerous (Zetterbaum 1987). Therefore,
economic inequality could pose serious problems in a procedural democracy.



Why, then, might inequality be so dangerous to democracy? According to Acemoglu
and Robinson (2006), unrest is often a consequence of inequality. And yet,
changes are more likely to occur in those societies with greater inequality
between elites and citizens. The more equals the society, the less likely are
the masses to demand democratization. Democratization requires that society be
sufficiently unequal so that the threat of revolution is credible. Therefore,
elite may be willing to begin a transition by extending the right of franchise
because it is in its interests to do so. The transition effectively preserves
the status quo by staving off the threat of revolution, which in the end may
preserve the power base of the elite. Yet, the elite only democratizes to the
degree necessary to stave off the threat of revolution, because the former
effectively limits the power of the majority by diluting popular pressure and
undermining the power of the majority. Democratization refers to achieving voice
through fair procedures. But democratization could mean achieving greater
equality through the redistribution of resources aimed at achieving equality of
result.

Economic equality, then, effectively promotes democracy because it effectively
reduces the pressure for redistribution, which could occur as a byproduct of
mass revolution and the subsequent creation of an authoritarian regime (Boix
2003). More unequal distribution of wealth increases the redistributive demands
of the population and the ultimate level of taxes in a democratic system. But
what happens when the political system is unresponsive to a so-called democratic
vote on the tax rate?

A truly democratic regime would not simply take away from the wealthy elite for
the benefit of the masses, but it might set a higher tax rate for purposes of
redistribution. In a democracy, everybody votes on the tax rate in accordance
with what is known as the median voter theorem. This holds that the more
inequality there is the greater will be the distance between the median income
and society’s average income. The greater the distance, the more calls there are
for redistribution, and it is the distance itself that effectively determines
the tax rate (Meltzer and Richard 1981).

On an individual level, unequal distribution of wealth and income, however, may
adversely affect individuals’ ability to participate in the democratic process
as equals. It may result in procedural inequality to the extent that those
lacking in wealth and income may not enjoy the same access to political and
policy officials as those who possess wealth and income enjoy. With a greater
concentration of wealth at the top, elites are in a better position to use their
wealth toward the attainment of their political and other ideological objectives
(Bachrach and Botwinick 1992: 4-5). Those at the top of the distribution often
enjoy inordinate power and are able to not only limit redistribution, but shape
the rules of the game in favor of those with more resources (Stiglitz 2012).
Various studies have found legislative bodies to be more responsive to affluent
constituents than to non-affluent constituents (Bartels 2008; Gilens 2012;
Volscho and Kelly 2012).

Inequality, especially in its extreme form of poverty, does in the end deprive
us of our capabilities, which is said to be a kind of freedom. To the extent
that individuals at the bottom of the income distribution could be said to be
poor, poverty deprives individuals of their capabilities. Therefore, there is a
strong case to be made for judging individual advantage in terms of the
capability that a person has — “the substantive freedoms he or she enjoys to
lead the kind of life he or she has reason to value” (Sen 1999, p.87). Such
freedoms are the basis of individual autonomy. Those with more resources may be
better positioned to pursue their goals and objectives, while those with fewer
resources may find that their ability to pursue their goals and objectives are
limited.

An individual’s ability to pursue their goals and objectives is important to
democracy for yet another reason. A democracy, especially as its legitimacy and
power are derived from popular consent, assumes that individuals have the
capacity to reason for themselves, i.e. to deliberate in the public square, and
to act on that capacity in a responsible manner. They cannot effectively
participate, whether it be in full policy discussions or selecting their own
representatives, if they cannot deliberate in a rational manner. As democracy
requires that individuals execute their agency, human agency must be protected.
But this human agency also presupposes that basic material needs will have been
met, which may be less likely given ever widening disparities in wealth and
income. Democracy also requires a measure of trust between people, and growing
income inequality is said to threaten trust as various groups, mainly those at
the bottom, experience political alienation and perceive the system not to be
fair. As social capital is the glue that holds society together (Stiglitz 2012),
if individuals believe that the economic and political system is unfair, the
glue does not work and society does not function well. This is
because institutions effectively promote trust. A trusting population tends to
be more cooperative, and governments with trusting populations tend to be less
corrupt and function with less conflict and greater responsiveness (Uslaner
2008).

Impact of Inequality on Civic Participation



Income inequality not only distorts democracy in terms of how institutions and
political actors respond to different levels of income, but it may have a
profound effect on the development of social capital, which affects civic
engagement. Democracy requires the active participation of citizens in the
affairs of their communities, which extends beyond mere voting. Underlying
social capital is the notion that civic virtue is most powerful when it is
embedded in a dense network of social relations. American civil society has been
defined by its associative life, in which Americans belong to voluntary
organizations. And through these organizations, they participate in the affairs
of their communities (Putnam 2000).

In a study of the relationship between income inequality and civic engagement,
Levin-Waldman (2013) found that in 2008 individuals in households with different
levels of income had different levels of civic engagement. Six measures of civic
engagement were considered: daily discussions of politics, daily reading of
newspapers — which were intended to speak to one’s knowledge about and interest
in politics — involvement in protests, attendance at political meetings,
visiting public officials, and participating in civic organizations.
Participation was found to be greater on all measures of participation among
those in households earning more than $100,000 a year than among those earning
less than $30,000. Those at the highest end of the distribution were not
necessarily more likely to be engaged than those between $30,000 and $99,999,
but those in households between $30,000 to $59,999 were considerably more likely
to be engaged than those in households below $30,000. Participation appeared to
improve dramatically when one was in a household with income greater than
$30,000. These differences alone would suggest that entry into the middle class
might result in greater levels of civic participation. Moreover, logistical
regressions found that those with higher incomes were more likely to be
civically engaged, and that those earning less than a minimum wage were least
likely to be engaged.

Aside from the adverse impact that income inequality has on civic engagement, it
could also lead to political anomie. As family income inequality increases,
those families below the median are further from the social norm than before.
Similarly, those at the top of the distribution see a larger gap between
themselves and the rest of the population. Families at the bottom of the
distribution may end up drifting further from the mainstream, and thus may also
experience greater alienation as those with greater resources may come to see
them as both more distinct and undeserving. This may also have consequences for
how citizens in turn view the potential role and functions of government
(Haveman, Sandefeur, Wolfe, and Voyer 2004). Poor people experience greater
social alienation because of their tendency to participate less, which means
that they may be out of touch with common interests. But participation is also
less likely because the alienation coming from social isolation will lead many
to the conclusion that there really is no benefit from participation in the
common project of which they are part. When resources are unequally distributed,
those at the top and the bottom might not see themselves as sharing the same
fate. Consequently, they have less reason to trust people of different
backgrounds. Where inequality is high, people may be less optimistic about being
masters of their own fate. Increasing inequality results in less participation
because of declining trust (Uslaner and Brown 2005).



Conclusion

With rising inequality, it ought to be clear that there are serious challenges
to democracy. It cannot be predicted with certainty just how disruptive
inequality will be to democracy, as this is contingent on the fragility of
democracy. In the U.S., we are clearly seeing an erosion in democracy in that
elected representatives no longer represent all people equally. Rather there is
greater responsiveness to those with resources, especially those contributing to
political campaigns. Increasingly those without resources find themselves frozen
out. In more fragile democracies, the response is unrest. And even in the U.S.
we see some of that with various social protest movements. Although the results
of the 2016 national election were not necessarily a response to rising income
inequality, they were clearly a response to the larger economic conditions of
which rising income inequality has been a symptom. Specifically, voters appeared
to be rebelling against political elites who apparently were unable to deliver
good job growth with rising wages. Voters chose a candidate who, rhetorically at
least, was opposed to open borders and free trade, and were effectively
challenging the commitment of elites to globalism — the same globalism that has
resulted in the two-tier economy with highly skilled and paid workers at the top
and poorly skilled and paid workers at the bottom. It might be a stretch to
conclude that the election of Donald Trump represents a desire for
authoritarianism. And yet, his critics view him as such, and if the voters were
not choosing what they might have thought were authoritarian solutions to
economic conditions, they were clearly responding to the very economic
conditions that have been the source of rising inequality in recent years.

Notes and References

[i]  Dividend income is income from stocks and/or other types of investments.

Acemoglu, Daron and James A. Robinson. 2006. Economic Origins of Dictatorship
and  Democracy. Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.

Bachrach, Peter and Aryeh Botwinick. 1992. Power and Empowerment: A Radical
Theory of Participatory Democracy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Bartels, Larry M. 2008. Unequal Democracy: The Political Economy of the New
Gilded Age. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Belman, Dale and Paul J. Wolfson. 2014. What Does the Minimum Wage
Do? Kalamazoo, MI: W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research.

Boix, Carles. 2003. Democracy and Redistribution. Cambridge and New York:
Cambridge University Press.

Gilens, Martin. 2012. Affluence & Influence: Economic Inequality and Political
Power in America. Princeton and New York: Princeton University Press/Russell
Sage Foundation.

Hacker, Jacob S. & Paul Pierson. 2010. Winner-Take-All Politics: How Washington
Made the Rich Richer — And Turned its Back on the Middle Class. New York: Simon
& Schuster.

Haveman, Robert, Gary Sandefeur, Barbara Wolfe, and Andrea Voyer. 2004. “Trends
in Children’s Attainments and Their Determinants as Family Income Inequality Has
Increased.” in Kathryn Neckerman ed., Social Inequality. New York: Russell Sage
Foundation.

Levin-Waldman, Oren M. 2013. “Income, Civic Participation and Achieving
Greater Democracy. Journal of Socio-Economics. 43,2:83-92.

Meltzer, Alan H. and Scott F. Richard. 1981. “A Rational Theory of the Size of
Government.” Journal of Political Economy. 89,5: 914-927.

Piketty, Thomas. 2014. Capital in the Twenty-First Century. Cambridge, MA and
London: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

Putnam, Robert. 2000. Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American
Community. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Anchor Books.

Stiglitz, Joseph E. 2012. The Price of Inequality. New York: W.W. Norton.

Uslaner, Eric. 2008. “The Foundations of Trust: Macro and Micro.” Cambridge
Journal of Economics. 32:289-294.

—————– and Mitchell Brown. 2005. “Inequality, Trust, and Civic
Engagement.” American Politics Research. 33,6 (November):868-894.

Volscho, Thomas W. Jr. and Nathan J. Kelly. 2012. “The Rise of the Super-Rich:
Power Resources, Taxes, Financial Markets, and the Dynamics of the Top 1
Percent, 1949-2008.” American Sociological Review. 77,5:679-699.

Zetterbaum, Marvin. 1987. “Alexis De Tocqueville.” In Leo Strauss and Joseph
Cropsey eds., History of Political Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.

Souce:






Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: Democracy,
Economics, income inequality, Inequality, Political Economy


THE GREATEST RESHUFFLE OF INDIVIDUAL INCOMES SINCE THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION

March 19, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


The effects of of globalization on income distributions in rich countries have
been studied extensively. This column takes a different approach by looking at
developments in global incomes from 1988 to 2008. Large real income gains have
been made by people around the median of the global income distribution and by
those in the global top 1%.  However, there has been an absence of real income
growth for people around the 80-85th percentiles of the global distribution, a
group consisting of people in ‘old rich’ OECD countries who are in the lower
halves of their countries’ income distributions.

The effects of trade, or more broadly of globalization, on incomes and their
distribution in the rich countries have been much studied, beginning with a
number of works on wage distributions in the 1990s, to more recent papers on the
effects of globalization on the labour share (Karabarbounis and Neiman 2013,
Elsby et al. 2013), wage inequality (Ebenstein et al. 2015), and routine middle
class jobs (Autor and Dorn 2010).

In joint work with Christoph Lakner (Lakner and Milanovic 2015) and in a
recently published book, Global Inequality: A New Approach for the Age of
Globalization (Milanovic 2016), Milanovic take a different approach of looking
at real incomes across the world population. This is made possible thanks to the
data from almost 600 household surveys from approximately 120 countries in the
world covering more than 90% of the world population and 95% of global GDP.
Since household surveys are not available for all countries annually, the data
are ‘centred’ on benchmark years, at five-year intervals, starting with 1988 and
ending in 2008. I report the results for up to 2011 in Milanovic (2016), while
Lakner has an unpublished update for 2013. The updates confirm, or reinforce,
the key findings for 1988-2008 that I discuss here.

The advantage of a global approach resides in its comprehensiveness and the
ability to observe and analyze the effects of globalization in many parts of the
world and on many parts of the global income distribution.  While the true or
putative effects of globalization on working class incomes in the rich world
have become the object of fierce political battles – especially in the wake of
the Brexit vote and the rise of Donald Trump to political prominence in the US –
the overall effects of globalization on the rest of the world have received less
attention, and when they have, were studied separately, as if independent, from
the effects observed in the rich word.

Figure 1 – dubbed by some ‘the elephant graph’ because of its shape – shows real
income gains realized at different percentiles of the global income distribution
between 1988 and 2008. Income is measured in 2005 international dollars and
individuals are ranked by their real household per capita income. The results
show large real income gains made by the people around the global median (point
A) and by those who are part of the global top 1% (point C).  It also shows an
absence of real income growth for the people around the 80-85th percentile of
the global distribution (point B). 



Figure 1. Cumulative real income growth between 1988 and 2008 at various
percentiles of the global income distribution

Who are the people at these three key points? Nine out of ten people around the
global median are from Asian countries, mostly from China and India. Their gains
are not surprising, given that Chinese and Indian GDP per capita has increased
by 5.6 and 2.3 times, respectively, over the period. Thus, for example, the
person at the median of the Chinese urban distribution in 1988 was then also at
the global median, but rose to the 63rd global percentile in 2008 and was above
the 70th percentile in 2011.  She thus leapfrogged, in terms of income, some 1.5
billion individuals. Such dramatic changes in relative income positions, over a
rather short time period, have not occurred since the Industrial Revolution two
centuries ago.



The people around the global median are, however, still relatively poor by
Western standards. This emerging ‘global middle class’ is composed of
individuals with household per capita incomes of between 5 and 15 international
dollars per day. To put these numbers into perspective, one should recall that
the national poverty lines in rich countries are often higher than 15 dollars
per person per day.  

The global top 1% is composed overwhelmingly of the people from the advanced
economies – one half of the people in that group are Americans, or differently
put, 12% of Americans are part of the global top 1%. China and India have many
billionaires (in effect, according to the 2015 Forbes list, China and India have
more than 300 billionaires versus more than 500 for the US), but compared to the
‘old rich’ world, Asian countries still do not have sufficient numbers of
‘comfortably rich’ or affluent households. In 2008, the threshold for being in
the global top 1% was 45,000 international dollars per person per year which,
translated into a traditional family structure of two partners and two children,
implies an after-tax income of $180,000 (or, using the approximate tax rates of
the rich countries, a before-tax income of more than $300,000).

The point that attracts most attention is B. Seven out of ten people at that
point are from the ‘old rich’ OECD countries. They belong to the lower halves of
their countries’ income distributions, for in effect the rich countries’ income
distributions start only around the 70th percentile of the global income
distribution. (For some especially rich and egalitarian advanced economies, that
start-up point is even higher – Denmark’s distribution begins around the 80th
global percentile.)

The contrast between the unambiguous success of people at point A and the
relative failure of people at point B allows us to look at the effects of
globalization more broadly. Not only can we see them more clearly when thus
juxtaposed, but it enables us to ask whether the two points are in some sense
related: is the absence of growth among lower middle classes of the rich world
the ‘cost’ paid for the high income gains of the national middle classes in
Asia? It is unlikely that one can provide a definitive answer to that question,
since establishing causality between such complex phenomena that are also
affected by a host of other variables is very difficult and perhaps impossible.
However, the temporal coincidence of the two developments and the plausible
narratives linking them, whether made by economists or by politicians, make the
correlation in many people’s mind appear real. 

In addition to looking at the global reshuffle of income through the
nation-state lenses (are the ‘losses’ of UK working class related to the gains
of the Chinese?), we can look at it through a purely cosmopolitan lens where all
individuals are treated equally, and the same-percentage income gains realized
by the poorer people are valued more than those made by the rich. With such a
perspective in mind, it would be hard to dismiss the period 1988-2008 (and as
our results for up to 2013 confirm, the period all the way to the present) as
being one of failure. One could, despite the rising income share of the global
top 1%, argue the opposite by pointing to the close to doubling of real incomes
realized by some one-fifth of the world population that lies between the 45th
and 65th global percentiles. It is their real income growth that has driven the
first decline in global inequality since the Industrial Revolution (Milanovic
2016, Chapter 1).  

The issue, however, is that such a cosmopolitan approach is a very abstract way
to look at the matters of distribution. Most people are concerned with their
incomes as compared to their national peers. Milanovic and Roemer (2016) show
that what seems a very positive development (that is, lower global inequality)
when individuals are assumed to be concerned solely with their absolute incomes
becomes much less positive when we also include in their welfare functions a
concern with relative positions in national income distributions. Then the
dominant feeling across the world, reflecting increasing national income
inequalities, becomes one of a relative loss.  

The political implications of a global ‘elephant graph’ are being played out in
national political spaces. In that space, rising national inequalities, despite
being accompanied by lower global poverty and inequality, may turn out to be
difficult to manage politically.


REFERENCES

Autor, D. and D. Dorn (2010), “The growth of low-skill service jobs and the
polarization of US labor market”, American Economic Review 103(5): 1553-97.  

Ebenstein, A., A. Harrison, M. McMillan and S. Phillips (2014), “Estimating the
Impact of Trade and Offshoring on American Workers Using the Current Population
Surveys”, Review of Economics and Statistics 96(4): 581–595.

Elsby, M. W. L., B. Hobijn, and A. Şahin (2013), “The Decline of US Labor
Share,” paper prepared for the Brookings Panel on Economic Activity, September
2013.

Karabarbounis, L. and B. Neiman (2013), “The Global Decline of the Labor
Share”, Quarterly Journal of Economics 129(1): 61–103.

Lakner, C. and B. Milanovic (2015), “Global income distribution: from the fall
of the Berlin Wall to the Great Recession”, World Bank Economic Review 30(2): 
203-232.

Milanovic, B. (2016), Global Inequality: A New Approach for the Age of
Globalization, Harvard University Press.  

Milanovic, B. and J. Roemer (2016), “Interaction of global and national income
inequalities”, Journal of Globalization and Development, forthcoming. 

Source:


Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: Globalization,
income distribution, Income Inequalities, Inequality


INTRODUCING KUZNETS WAVES: HOW INCOME INEQUALITY WAXES AND WANES OVER THE VERY
LONG RUN

March 18, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


The Kuznets curve was widely used to describe the relationship between growth
and inequality over the second half of the 20th century, but it has fallen out
of favour in recent decades. This column suggests that the current upswing in
inequality can be viewed as a second Kuznets curve. It is driven, like the
first, by technological progress, inter-sectoral reallocation of labour,
globalization, and policy. The author argues that the US has still not reached
the peak of inequality in this second Kuznets wave of the modern era.

In 1955 when Simon Kuznets wrote about the movement of inequality in rich
countries (and a couple of poor ones), the US and the UK were in the midst of
the most significant decrease of income inequality ever registered in history,
coupled with fast growth. It thus seemed eminently reasonable to look at the
factors behind the decrease of inequality, and Kuznets famously found them in
expanded education, lower inter-sectoral productivity differences (thus the rent
component of wages would be equalized), lower return to capital, and political
pressure for greater social transfers. He then looked at (or rather imagined)
the evolution of inequality during the previous century and thought that, driven
by the transfer of labour from agriculture to manufacturing, inequality rose and
reached its peak in the rich world sometime around the turn of the 20th century.
Thus, he created the famous Kuznets curve.

The Kuznets curve was the main tool used by inequality economists when thinking
about the relationship between development or growth and inequality over the
past half century. But the Kuznets curve gradually fell out of favor because its
prediction of low inequality in very rich societies could not be squared with
the sustained increase in income inequality that started in the late 1970s in
practically all developed nations (see the long-run graphs for the US and the
UK). Many people thus rejected it.


THE UPSWING IN CURRENT INEQUALITY AS A SECOND KUZNETS CURVE



In a new book (Milanovic 2016), I argue however that we should see the current
upswing in inequality as the second Kuznets curve in the modern times, being
driven, like the first, mostly by a technological revolution and the transfer of
labour from more homogenous manufacturing into skill-heterogeneous services (and
thus producing a decline in the ability of workers to organize), but also (again
like the first) by globalization, which has both led to the famous hollowing out
of the middle classes in the west and to a pressure to reduce high tax rates on
mobile capital and high-skilled labour. The elements listed here are not new.
But putting them together (especially viewing technological progress and
globalization as practically indissoluble, even if conceptually different) and
viewing this as part of regular Kuznets waves is new. It has obvious
implications for the future, not the least that this bout of inequality growth
will peak like the previous one and eventually go down.

But  before I address that part, let us consider recent important work done by
economic historians such as van Zayden (1995); Nogal and Prados (2013); Alfani
(2014) and Ryckbosch (2014), who have documented periods of waxing and waning
inequality in pre-modern Europe. The interesting part is that Kuznets cycles in
pre-modern societies basically replicate the Malthusian cycles because they take
place in conditions of quasi-stationary mean income. The pre-modern Kuznets
cycles are not driven by economic factors but by epidemics and wars. Both lead
to a decrease in population, an increase in mean income, higher wages (because
of labour scarcity) and thus lower inequality, that is, until population growth
in a Malthusian fashion reverses all these gains.



Thus, we can observe Kuznets waves over some six or seven centuries of European
history. In pre-modern times, they are observable against time because mean
income is more or less constant (it is just one point on the x-axis). After the
Industrial Revolution, however, we see the waves responding to economic factors
(e.g. technological change, transfer of labour), and can plot them as Kuznets
thought against mean income. This is shown here in the graphs for the US and the
UK (Figure 1 and 2). In addition, I show in my book long-term inequality cycles
for Spain, Italy, the Netherlands, Germany, Japan, Brazil, Chile, and over a
shorter period for China.

Source: Ginis: 1774, 1850, 1860 and 1870 from social tables created by Lindert
and Williamson (2013); 1929. Radner and Hinricks (1974);  1931 and 1933:
Smolensky and Plotnick (1992). From 1935 to 1950 from Goldsmith et al (1954);
After 1950, from US Census Bureau, Income, poverty and health insurance coverage
in the United States (various issues); gross income data adjusted to reflect
disposable income. GDP per capita from Maddison project 2014 version.
Source: Ginis: for 1688, 1759, 1801, and 1867 from social tables for England/UK
(as reported in Milanovic, Lindert and Williamson, 2011); for 1880 and 1913,
from Lindert and Williamson (1983, Table 2); from 1961 to 2010, official UK data
(disposable income per capita) kindly calculated and provided by Jonathan Cribb,
Institute for Fiscal Studies. GDP per capita from Maddison project 2014 version.

While Kuznets’ explanation was focused almost entirely on economic and thus
‘benign’ forces, he was wrong to overlook the impact of ‘malign’ forces
(especially wars) that are powerful engines of income equalisation. I find this
somewhat puzzling because Kuznets himself, having worked during World War II in
the US Bureau of Planning and Statistics, must have noticed how the war led to
the compression of income through higher taxation, financial repression,
rationing, price controls, and even sheer destruction of physical assets (as in
Europe and Japan).


INEQUALITY MAY NOT BE OVERTURNED SOON





Which leads us to the present. How long will the current upswing of the Kuznets
wave continue in the rich world, and when and how will it stop? I am skeptical
that it will be overturned soon, at least not in the US where I see four
powerful forces that keep on pushing inequality up. I will just list them here
(they are, of course, discussed in the book):

 * Rising share of capital income which is in all rich countries extremely
   concentrated among the rich (with a Gini in excess of 90);
 * Growing association of high incomes from both capital and labour in the hands
   of the same people (Atkinson and Lakner 2014);
 * Homogamy (the educated and the rich marrying each other); and
 * Growing importance of money in politics which allows the rich to write rules
   favourable to them and thus to maintain the inequality momentum (Gilens
   2012).

The peak of inequality in the second Kuznets wave should be lower than in the
first (when in the UK, it was equal to the inequality level of today’s South
Africa) because the rich societies have in the meantime acquired a number of
‘inequality stabilizers’, from unemployment benefits to state pensions.

The pro-inequality trends will be very hard to overturn during the next
generation, but eventually they may be – through a combination of political
change, pro-unskilled labour technological innovations (which will become more
profitable as skilled labor’s price increases), dissipation of rents acquired
during the current bout of technological efflorescence, and possibly greater
attempts to equalize ownership of assets (through forms of ‘people’s capitalism’
and workers’ shareholding).   

Now, these are of course the benign factors that, I think, will ultimately set
inequality in rich countries on its downward path. But history teaches us too
that there are malign factors, notably wars, in turn caused by domestic
maldistribution of income and power of the elites (as was the case in the World
War I), that can also do the job of income levelling. But they do it at the cost
of millions of human lives. One can hope that we have learned something from
history and would avoid this destructive path to equality in poverty and death.


REFERENCES

Alfani, G (2014), “Economic inequality in the northwestern Italy: a long-term
view (fourteenth to eighteenth century)”, Dondena Working Paper No. 61, Bocconi
University, Milano.

Alvarez-Nogal, C and L Prados de la Escosura (2013), “The rise and fall of Spain
(1270–1850),” Economic History Review, vol. 66(1), pages 1-37. 

Atkinson, A and C Lakner (2014), “Wages, capital and top incomes: The factor
income composition of top incomes in the USA, 1960-2005”, November version.

Gilens, M(2012), Affluence and Influence, Princeton University Press.

Kuznets, S (1955), “Economic growth and income inequality”, American Economic
Review, March, pp. 1-28.

Milanovic, B (2016), Global inequality: A new approach for the age of
globalization, Harvard University Press.

Ryckbosch, W (2014), “Economic inequality and growth before the Industrial
Revolution: A case study of Low countries (14th-16th century), Dondena Working
Paper No. 67, Bocconi University, Milano.

van Zanden, J L (1995), “Tracing the beginning of the Kuznets curve: western
Europe during the early modern period”, The Economic History Review, vol. 48,
issue 4, pp. 1-23. November. 

Source:




Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: Development
Economics, economic developments, Economics, Economics Inequality, Political
Economy


WEALTH AND INCOME DISTRIBUTION: NEW THEORIES NEEDED FOR A NEW ERA

March 17, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


Growth theories traditionally focus on the Kaldor-Kuznets stylised facts. Ravi
Kanbur and Nobelist Joe Stiglitz argue that these no longer hold; new theory is
needed. The new models need to drop competitive marginal productivity theories
of factor returns in favour of rent-generating mechanism and wealth inequality
by focusing on the ‘rules of the game.’ They also must model interactions among
physical, financial, and human capital that influence the level and evolution of
inequality. A third key component will be to capture mechanisms that transmit
inequality from generation to generation.

Six decades ago, Nicholas Kaldor (1957) put forward a set of stylized facts on
growth and distribution for mature industrial economies. The first and most
prominent of these was the constancy of the share of capital relative to that of
wealth in national income. At about the same time, Simon Kuznets (1955) put
forward a second set of stylized facts — that while the interpersonal inequality
of income distribution might increase in the early stages of development, it
declines as industrialized economies mature.

These empirical formulations brought forth a generation of growth and
development theories whose object was to explain the stylised facts. Kaldor
himself presented a growth model which claimed to produce outcomes consistent
with constancy of factor shares, as did Robert Solow. Kuznets also developed a
model of rural-urban transition consistent with his prediction, as did many
others (Kanbur 2012).


KALDOR-KUZNETS FACTS NO LONGER HOLD

However, the Kaldor-Kuznets stylized facts no longer hold for advanced
economies. The share of capital as conventionally measured has been on the rise,
as has interpersonal inequality of income and wealth. Of course, there are
variations and subtleties of data and interpretation, and the pattern is not
uniform. But these are the stylized facts of our time. Bringing these facts
centre stage has been the achievement of research leading up to Piketty (2014).

It stands to reason that theories developed to explain constancy of factor
shares cannot explain a rising share of capital. The theories developed to
explain the earlier stylized facts cannot very easily explain the new trends, or
the turnaround. At the same time, rising inequality has opened once again a set
of questions on the normative significance of inequality of outcomes versus
inequality of opportunity. New theoretical developments are needed for positive
and normative analysis in this new era.

What sort of new theories? In the realm of positive analysis, Piketty has
himself put forward a theory based on the empirical observation that the rate of
return to capital, r, systematically exceeds the rate of growth, g; the famous r
> g relation. Much of the commentary on Piketty’s facts and theorizing has tried
to make the stylized fact of rising share of capital consistent with a standard
production function F (K, L) with capital ‘K’ and labour ‘L’. But in this
framework a rising share of capital can be consistent with the other stylised
fact of rising capital-output ratio only if the elasticity of substitution
between capital and labour is greater than unity, which is not consistent with
the broad  empirical findings (Stiglitz, 2014a). Further, what Piketty and
others measure as wealth ‘W’ is a measure of control over resources, not a
measure of capital K, in the sense that that is used in the context of a
production function.


DIFFERENCES BETWEEN K AND W

There is a fundamental distinction between capital K, thought of as physical
inputs to production, and wealth W, thought of as including land and the
capitalized value of other rents which give command over purchasing power. This
distinction will be crucial in any theorizing to explain the new stylized facts.
‘K’ can be going down even as ‘W’ increases; and some increases in W may
actually lower economic productivity. In particular, new theories explaining the
evolution of inequality will have to address directly changes in rents and their
capitalized value (Stiglitz 2014). Two examples will illustrate what we have in
mind.

 * Consider first the case of all sea-front property on the French Riviera.



As demand for these properties rises, perhaps from rich foreigners seeking a
refuge for their funds, the value of sea frontage will be bid up. The current
owners will get rents from their ownership of this fixed factor. Their wealth
will go up and their ability to command purchasing power in the economy will
rise correspondingly. But the actual physical input to production has not
increased. All else constant, national output will not rise; there will only be
a pure distributional effect.

 * Consider the case where the government gives an implicit guarantee to bail
   out banks.

This contingent support to income flows from ownership of bank shares will be
capitalised into the value of these shares. Of course, there is an equal and
opposite contingent liability on all others in the economy, in particular on
workers — the owners of human capital. Again, without any necessary impact on
total output, the political economy has created rents for share owners, and the
increase in their wealth will be reflected in rising inequality. One can see
this without going through a conventional production function analysis. Of
course, the rents once created will provide further resources for rentiers to
lobby the political system to maintain and further increase rents. This will set
 in  motion a spiral of increasing inequality, which again does not go through
the production system at all — except to the extent that the associated
distortions represent a downward shift in the productivity of the economy (at
any level of inputs of ‘K’ and labour).

Analysing the role of land rents in increases in inequality can be done in a
variant of standard neoclassical models — by expanding inputs to include land;
but explaining increase in inequality as a result of an increase in other forms
of rent will need a theory of rents which takes us beyond the competitive
determination of factor rewards.


DIFFERENCES IN INEQUALITY: CAPITAL INCOME VERSUS LABOUR INCOME

The translation from factor shares to interpersonal inequality has usually been
made through the assumption that capital income is more unequally distributed
than labour income. Inequality of capital ownership then translates into
inequality of capital income, while inequality of income from labour is assumed
to be much smaller. The assumption is made in its starkest form in models where
there are owners of capital who save and workers who do not.

These stylised assumptions no longer provide a fully satisfactory explanation of
income inequality because: (i) there is more widespread ownership of wealth
through life cycle savings in various forms including pensions; and (ii)
increasingly unequal returns to increasingly unequally distributed human capital
has led to sharply rising inequality of labour income.

Sharply rising inequality of labour income focuses attention on inequality of
human capital in its most general sense:

 * Starting with unequal prenatal development of the foetus;
 * Followed by unequal early childhood development and investments by parents;
 * Unequal educational investments by parents and society; and
 * Unequal returns to human capital because of discrimination at one end and use
   of parental connections in the job market at the other end.

Discrimination continues to play a role, not only in the determination of factor
returns given the ownership of assets, including human capital; but also on the
distribution of asset ownership.

 * At each step, inequality of parental resources is translated into inequality
   of children’s outcomes.

An exploration of this type of inequality requires a different type of empirical
and theoretical  analysis from  the conventional macro-level analysis of
production functions and factor shares (Heckman and Mosso, 2014, Stiglitz,
2015).

In particular, intergenerational transmission of inequality is more than simple
inheritance of physical and financial wealth. Layered upon genetic inequalities
are the inequalities of parental resources. Income inequality across parents,
due to inequality of income from physical and financial capital on the one hand,
and inequality due to inequality of human capital on the other, is translated
into inequality of financial and human capital of the next generation. Human
capital inequality perpetuates itself through intergenerational transmission
just as wealth inequality caused by politically created rents perpetuates
itself.

Given such transmission across generations, it can be shown that the long-run,
‘dynastic’ inequality will also be higher (Kanbur and Stiglitz 2015). Although
there have been advances in recent years, we still need fully developed theories
of how the different mechanisms interact with each other to explain the dramatic
rises in interpersonal inequality in advanced economies in the last three
decades.1


HIGH INEQUALITY: NEW REALITIES AND OLD DEBATES

The new realities of high inequality have revived old debates on policy
interventions and their ethical and economic rationale (Stiglitz 2012). Standard
analysis which balances the tradeoff between efficiency and equity would suggest
that taxation should now become more progressive to balance the greater inherent
inequality against the incentive effects of progressive taxation (Kanbur and
Tuomala,1994 ).



One counter argument is that what matters is not inequality of ‘outcome’ but
inequality of ‘opportunity’. According to this argument, so long as the
prospects are the same for all children, the inequality of income across parents
should not matter ethically. What we should aim for is equality of opportunity,
not income equality. However, when income inequality across parents translates
into inequality of prospects across children, even starting in the womb, then
the distinction between opportunity and income begins to fade and the case for
progressive taxation is not undermined by the ‘equality of opportunity’
objective (Kanbur and Wagstaff 2015).


CONCLUDING REMARKS

Thus, the new stylised facts of our era demand new theories of income
distribution.

 * First, we need to break away from competitive marginal productivity theories
   of factor returns and model mechanisms which generate rents with consequences
   for wealth inequality.

This will entail a greater focus on the ‘rules of the game.’ (Stiglitz et al
2015).

 * Second, we need to focus on the interaction between income from physical and
   financial capital and income from human capital in determining snapshot
   inequality, but also in determining the intergenerational transmission of
   inequality.
 * Third, we need to further develop normative theories of equity which can
   address mechanisms of inequality transmission from generation to generation.2


REFERENCES

Bevan, D and J E Stiglitz (1979), “Intergenerational Transfers and
Inequality”, The Greek Economic Review, 1(1), August, pp. 8-26.

Heckman, J and S Mosso (2014), “The Economics of Human Development and Social
Mobility”, Annual Reviews of Economics, 6: 689-733.

Kaldor, N (1957), “A Model of Economic Growth”, The Economic Journal, 67(268):
591-624.

Kanbur, R (2012), “Does Kuznets Still Matter?” in S. Kochhar
(ed.), Policy-Making for Indian Planning: Essays on Contemporary Issues in Honor
of Montek S. Ahluwalia, Academic Foundation Press, pp. 115-128, 2012.

Kanbur, R and J E Stiglitz (2015), “Dynastic Inequality, Mobility and Equality
of Opportunity“, CEPR Discussion Paper No. 10542.

Kanbur, R and M Tuomala (1994), ‘‘Inherent Inequality and the Optimal Graduation
of Marginal Tax Rates”, (with M. Tuomala), Scandinavian Journal of Economics,
Vol. 96, No. 2, pp. 275-282, 1994.

Kuznets, S (1955), “Economic Growth and Income Inequality”, The American
Economic Review, 45(1): 1-28.

Piketty, T (2014), Capital in the Twenty-First Century, Cambridge Massachusetts:
The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

Piketty, T, E Saez, and S Stantcheva (2011), “Taxing the 1%: Why the top tax
rate could be over 80%”, VoxEU.org, 8 December.

Roemer, J E and A Trannoy (2014), “Equality of Opportunity”, in A B Atkinson and
F Bourguignon (eds.) Handbook of Income Distribution SET Vols 2A-2B. Elsevier.

Stiglitz, J E, et. al. (2015) “Rewriting the Rules of the American
Economy“, Roosevelt Institute.

Stiglitz, J E (1969), “Distribution of Income and Wealth Among
Individuals”, Econometrica, 37(3), July, pp. 382-397. (Presented at the December
1966 meetings of the Econometric Society, San Francisco.)

Stiglitz, J E (2012), The Price of Inequality: How Today’s Divided Society
Endangers Our Future, New York: W.W. Norton.

Stiglitz, J E (2014), “New Theoretical Perspectives on the Distribution of
Income and Wealth Among Individuals”, paper presented to the International
Economic Association World Congress, Dead Sea, June and forthcoming
in Inequality and Growth: Patterns and Policy, Volume 1: Concepts and Analysis,
to be published by Palgrave MacMillan.

Stiglitz, J E (2015), “New Theoretical Perspectives on the Distribution of
Income and Wealth Among Individuals: Parts I-IV”, NBER Working Papers
21189-21192, May.


FOOTNOTES

1 For early discussions of such transmission processes, see Stiglitz(1969) and
Bevan and Stiglitz (1979).  

2 Developments in this area are exemplified by Roemer and Trannoy (2014).

Source:


Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: Development
Economics, Economics, Inequality, policy, Political Economy


INCOME INEQUALITY AND CITIZENSHIP: QUANTIFYING THE LINK

March 16, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


Our level of income is unarguably dependent on where we live in the world. But
evidencing this is tricky. This Posting presents a model that explains global
income variability using one variable only – where you live. The results suggest
that we might want to reassess how we think about both economic migration and
global inequality of opportunity.

It is as obvious as it is well known that the world is unequal in terms of
individuals’ incomes (e.g. Mohammed 2015).  But it is unequal in a very
particular way – when split into ‘inequality within countries’ and ‘inequality
between countries’, the latter accounts for by far the biggest gap.

Inequality within countries measures, for instance, gaps between poor and rich
Americans or between poor and rich Chinese. For simplicity, let’s call it
‘class’ inequality. But there is also another equally obvious inequality – that
between rich and poor nations. More specifically, this inequality is measured as
the gap between the ‘representative’ or ‘average’ individuals of any two
countries, be they Morocco and Spain or Mexico and the US. For simplicity, let’s
call this ‘locational’ inequality.

Inequality, as it is commonly understood in today’s world, is such that whatever
measure we choose, the lion’s share of global inequality is ‘explained’ by the
differences in mean incomes between countries.

This was not always the case. Although our data for the past are far more
tentative than our data for today’s global income distribution, we can still
state with little doubt that the dominant type of equality in the 19th century
was that within countries (see Milanovic 2011).


CITIZENSHIP PREMIUMS AND PENALTIES

If income differences between countries are large then your income will
significantly depend on where you live, or even on where you were born (97% of
the world’s population remain in the countries where they were born). This is
what I call a ‘citizenship premium’ (or a ‘citizenship penalty’) – a ‘rent’ that
a person receives if he or she happens to be born in a rich country, or, if we
use the terminology introduced by John Roemer, an ‘exogenous circumstance’ which
is independent from any one individual’s effort and episodic luck (Roemer 2000).

How big is citizenship rent, how does it vary with one’s position in the income
distribution, and what does it imply for global inequality of opportunity and
migration?


ESTIMATING CITIZENSHIP RENT

I estimate citizenship rent by using data collected from household surveys
conducted in 118 countries in and around the year 2008 (Milanovic 2015). For
each country, I have micro-level (household) data ordered into 100 percentiles,
with individuals ranked by their household per capita income. This gives 11,800
country/percentiles with ‘representative’ per capita incomes expressed in
dollars of equal purchasing parity, making incomes across countries comparable.

I ‘explain’ these incomes using only one variable – the country where
individuals live. Of course, people living in the US will tend to have higher
incomes at any given percentile of the distribution than people living in poor
countries in, for instance, Africa. But how will it look for the world as a
whole? In a least-square dummy variable regression, I use Congo (the poorest
county in the world) as the ‘omitted country’ so that I can express the
citizenship premium in every other country in terms of the income gain compared
to Congo. The premium for the US is 355%, it is 329% for Sweden and 164% for
Brazil. But for Yemen, another very poor country, it’s 32%.

According to this regression, we can explain more than two-thirds of the
variability in incomes across country/percentiles by only one variable – the
country where people live. This estimation shows that, as we thought, a lot of
our income depends on where we live.


CITIZENSHIP RENT ACROSS THE DISTRIBUTION      

But this is only an average premium that compares countries. Does citizenship
rent vary along the entire income distribution? If I were to take into
consideration only people belonging to the lowest part of the income
distribution in each country, would the premium still be the same?

Intuition may help here. Suppose that I focus only on the incomes of the lowest
decile (with rich countries more equal than poor countries). Then the gap
between rich and poor countries should be greater for the very poor people than
for the average individual.  And this is indeed what we find – Sweden’s
citizenship premium compared to Congo is now 367% versus 329% on average. But
Brazil’s is 133% versus 164%.  The situation at the top is exactly the opposite
– Sweden’s advantaged position at the 90th percentile of the income distribution
is ‘only’ 286%, but Brazil’s becomes 188%.


IMPLICATIONS FOR MIGRATION

The existence of the citizenship premium has obvious implications for migration:
people from poor countries will have the opportunity to double or triple their
real incomes by moving to a rich country.

But the fact that the premium varies as a function of one’s position in the
income distribution carries additional implications. If I consider moving to one
of two countries that have the same average income, my decision on where to
migrate – based on economic criteria alone – will also be influenced by my
expectations regarding where I may end up in the recipient county’s income
distribution. My decision will thus be influenced by the extent to which the
recipient country’s income distribution is unequal.



Suppose that Sweden and the US have the same mean income. If I expect to end up
in the bottom part of a recipient country’s distribution, then I should migrate
to Sweden. The poor people in Sweden are better off compared to the mean, and
the citizenship premium, evaluated at lower parts of distribution, is greater.
The opposite conclusion follows if I expect to end up in the upper part of the
recipient country’s distribution – I should migrate to the US.

This last result has unpleasant implications for rich countries with greater
‘in-country’ equality. More equal rich countries will tend to attract
lower-skilled migrants who generally expect to be placed in the bottom part of
the recipient country’s distribution. Developing a national welfare state would
have the perverse effect of attracting migrants who can contribute less.

Even in this rough sketch, we also have to consider the levels of social
mobility in recipient countries because more unequal countries with strong
social mobility will, everything else being the same, tend to appeal to more
skilled migrants.


GLOBAL INEQUALITY OF OPPORTUNITY

The mere existence of a large citizenship premium implies that there is no such
a thing as global equality of opportunity because a lot of our income depends on
the accident of birth.

So should we strive for global equality of opportunity or not? It is a political
philosophy question that philosophers have thought much more about than
economists. Some, following John Rawls in The Law of Peoples, believe that this
is not an issue and that every argument for global equality of opportunity would
conflict with the right of national self-determination. But other political
philosophers like Thomas Pogge believe that in an interdependent world, the
dominant role of chance in people’s life is not to be accepted lightly (Pogge
2008). I am not proposing a solution to this issue, yet, I believe that
economists should not shy away from addressing it.1

As gaps between nations diminish, mostly thanks to the high growth rates of
Asian countries, the citizenship rent will tend to reduce. But there is such a
huge gap today that even a century of much higher growth in poor countries (in
comparison to rich countries) will not eradicate citizenship rent.

However, it will reduce. As it does, it will also reduce overall global
inequality. This might then lead us to a world not dissimilar to the mid-19th
century, in which class is again more important for one’s global income position
than location.

Do I hear the distant sound of Marx?


REFERENCES

Milanovic, B (2011), The haves and the have-nots: a short and idiosyncratic
history of global inequality, New York: Basic Books.

Milanovic, B (2015), “Global Inequality of Opportunity: How Much of Our Income
Is Determined By Where We Live?”, The Review of Economics and Statistics 97(2):
452-460.

Mohammed, A (2015), “Deepening income inequality”, World Economic Forum report.

Pogge, T (2008), World Poverty and Human Rights, Polity Press.

Rawls, J (2001), The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Roemer, J (2000), Equality of Opportunity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.

Shachar, A (2009), The Birthright Lottery, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.


FOOTNOTE

1 Legal scientists such as Ayalet Shachar have written about addressing global
inequality from a legal standpoint, proposing a much more flexible and open
definition of citizenship (see Shachar 2009).

Source:


Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: Citizenship,
Economics, global inequality, Inequality, policy, Political Economy, Politics


GLOBAL INCOME DISTRIBUTION: FROM THE FALL OF THE BERLIN WALL TO THE
GREAT RECESSION

March 15, 2022 Namoura Coffee Leave a comment


Since 1988, rapid growth in Asia has lifted billions out of poverty. Incomes at
the very top of the world income distribution have also grown rapidly, whereas
median incomes in rich countries have grown much more slowly. This posting asks
whether these developments, while reducing global income inequality overall,
might undermine democracy in rich countries.

The period between the fall of the Berlin Wall and the Great Recession saw
probably the most profound reshuffle of individual incomes on the global scale
since the Industrial Revolution. This was driven by high growth rates of
populous and formerly poor or very poor countries like China, Indonesia, and
India; and, on the other hand, by the stagnation or decline of incomes in
sub-Saharan Africa and post-communist countries as well as among poorer segments
of the population in rich countries.



Anand and Segal (2008) offer a detailed review of the work on global income
inequality. In Lakner and Milanovic (2013), we address some of the limitations
of these earlier studies and present new results from detailed work on household
survey data from about 120 countries over the period 1988–2008. Each country’s
distribution is divided into ten deciles (each decile consists of 10% of the
national population) according to their per capita disposable income (or
consumption). In order to make incomes comparable across countries and time,
they are corrected both for domestic inflation and differences in price levels
between countries. It is then possible to observe not only how the position of
different countries changes over time – as we usually do – but also how the
position of various deciles within each country changes. For example, Japan’s
top decile remained at the 99th (2nd highest from the top) world percentile, but
Japan’s median decile dropped from the 91st to the 88th global percentile. Or,
to take another example, the top Chinese urban decile moved from being in the
68th global percentile in 1988 to being in the 83rd global percentile in 2008,
thus leapfrogging in the process some 15% of the world population – equivalent
to almost a billion people.

When we line up all individuals in the world, from the poorest to the richest
(going from left to right on the horizontal axis in Figure 1), and display on
the vertical axis the percentage increase in the real income of the equivalent
group over the period 1988–2008, we generate a global growth incidence curve –
the first of its kind ever, because such data at the global level were not
available before. The curve has an unusual supine S shape, indicating that the
largest gains were realised by the groups around the global median (50th
percentile) and among the global top 1%. But after the global median, the gains
rapidly decrease, becoming almost negligible around the 85th–90th global
percentiles and then shooting up for the global top 1%. As a result, growth in
the income of the top ventile (top 5%) accounted for 44% of the increase in
global income between 1988 and 2008.

Figure 1.Anonymous global growth incidence curve: Real income change at various
percentiles of the global income distribution between 1988 and 2008 (%)

Fortunes of income deciles in different countries over time

The curve in Figure 1 is drawn using a simple comparison of real income levels
at given percentiles of the global income distribution in 1988 and 2008. It is
‘anonymous’ because it does not tell us what happened to the actual people who
were at given global income percentiles in the initial year, 1988. In fact, the
regional composition of the different global income groups changed radically
over time because growth was uneven across regions. A ‘quasi non-anonymous’
growth incidence curve in Figure 2 adjusts for this – the growth rates are
calculated for all individual country/deciles at the positions they held in the
initial year (1988). The growth rate on the vertical axis (calculated from a
non-parametric fit) thus shows how the country/deciles that were poor,
middle-class, rich, etc. in 1988 performed over the next 20 years. The supine S
shape still remains, although it is now slightly less dramatic.

People around the median almost doubled their real incomes. Not surprisingly, 9
out of 10 such ‘winners’ were from the ‘resurgent Asia’. For example, a person
around the middle of the Chinese urban income distribution saw his or her 1988
real income multiplied by a factor of almost 3; someone in the middle of the
Indonesian or Thai income distribution by a factor of 2, Indian by a factor of
1.4, etc.

It is perhaps less expected that people who gained the least were almost
entirely from the ‘mature economies’ – OECD members that include also a number
of former communist countries. But even when the latter are excluded, the
overwhelming majority in that group of ‘losers’ are from the ‘old, conventional’
rich world. But not just anyone from the rich world. Rather, the ‘losers’ were
predominantly the people who in their countries belong to the lower halves of
national income distributions. Those around the median of the German income
distribution have gained only 7% in real terms over 20 years; those in the US,
26%. Those in Japan lost out in real terms.

Figure 2 Quasi non-anonymous global growth incidence curve: Real income change
between 1988 and 2008 across 1988 percentiles of the global income distribution

The particular supine S-shaped growth incidence curve (Figure 1) does not allow
us to immediately tell whether global inequality might have gone up or down
because the gains around the median (which tend to reduce inequality) may be
offset by the gains of the global top 1% (which tend to increase inequality). On
balance, however, it turns out that the first element dominates, and that global
inequality – as measured by most conventional indicators – went down. The global
Gini coefficient fell by almost 2 Gini points (from 72.2 to 70.5) during the
past 20 years of globalisation. Was it then all for the better?



Probably yes, but not so simply. The striking association of large gains around
the median of the global income distribution – received mostly by the Asian
populations – and the stagnation of incomes among the poor or lower middle
classes in rich countries, naturally opens the question of whether the two are
associated. Does the growth of China and India take place on the back of the
middle class in rich countries? There are many studies that, for particular
types of workers, discuss the substitutability between rich countries’
low-skilled labour and Asian labour embodied in traded goods and services or
outsourcing. Global income data do not allow us to establish or reject the
causality. But they are quite suggestive that the two phenomena may be related.

Figure 3 Real per capita income of the 2nd income decile in the US and the 8th
urban income decile in China between 1988 and 2011

A dramatic way to see the change brought by globalisation is to compare the
evolution over time of the 2nd US income decile with (say) the Chinese urban 8th
decile (Figure 3). Indeed we are comparing relatively poor people in the US with
relatively rich people in China, but given the income differences between the
two countries, and that the two groups may be thought to be in some kind of
global competition, the comparison makes sense. Here we extend the analysis to
2011, using more recent and preliminary data. While the real income of the US
2nd decile has increased by some 20% in a quarter century, the income of China’s
8th decile has been multiplied by a factor of 6.5. The absolute income gap,
still significant five years ago, before the onset of the Great Recession, has
narrowed substantially.

Political Implications

And even if the causality cannot be established because of many technical
difficulties and an inability to define credible counterfactuals, the
association between the two cannot pass unnoticed. What, then, are its
implications? First, will the bottom incomes of the rich countries continue to
stagnate as the rest of China, or later Indonesia, Nigeria, India, etc. follow
the upward movement of Chinese workers through the ranks of the global income
distribution? Does this imply that the developments that are indeed profoundly
positive from the global point of view may prove to be destabilising for
individual rich countries?

Second, if we take a simplistic, but effective, view that democracy is
correlated with a large and vibrant middle class, its continued hollowing-out in
the rich world would, combined with growth of incomes at the top, imply a
movement away from democracy and towards forms of plutocracy. Could then the
developing countries, with their rising middle classes, become more democratic
and the US, with its shrinking middle class, less?

Third, and probably the most difficult: What would such movements, if they
continue for a couple of decades, imply for global stability? The formation of a
global middle class, or the already perceptible ‘homogenisation’ of the global
top 1%, regardless of their nationality, may be both deemed good for world
stability and interdependency, and socially bad for individual countries as the
rich get ‘delinked’ from their fellow citizens.

Conclusion

In a nutshell, the movements that we witness do not only lead to an economic
rebalancing of the East and West – in which both may end up with global output
shares close to what they had before the Industrial Revolution – but to a
contradiction between the current world order, where political power is
concentrated at the level of the nation-state, and the economic forces of
globalization which have gone far beyond it.

References

Anand, Sudhir and Paul Segal (2008), “What Do We Know about Global Income
Inequality?”, Journal of Economic Literature, 46(1): 57–94.

Lakner, Christoph and Branko Milanovic (2013), “Global income distribution: from
the fall of the Berlin Wall to the Great Recession”, World Bank Working Paper
No. 6719, December.

Source:


Categories: Comments and Reflection, DISCUSSION PAPERS Tags: Economics,
Globalization, income distribution, income inequality, policy, Political
Economy, Politics
Older Entries

RSS feed
 * Google
 * Youdao
 * Xian Guo
 * Zhua Xia
 * My Yahoo!
 * newsgator
 * Bloglines
 * iNezha


Search for:


RECENT POSTS

 * The Separation of the ‘Economic’ and the ‘Political’ under Capitalism:
   ‘Capital-centric Marxism’ and the Capitalist State
 * Can Democracy Reduce Inequality
 * The Wage Curve across the Wealth Distribution
 * Capitalist Systems and Income Inequality
 * How Inequality Undermines Democracy?


ARCHIVES

Archives Select Month March 2022 February 2022 July 2021 June 2021 February 2021
January 2021 December 2020 November 2020 October 2020 September 2020 August 2020
January 2020 December 2019 August 2019 July 2019 February 2019 October 2018
September 2018 September 2017 May 2017 December 2016 November 2016 March 2016
January 2016 September 2015 November 2014 March 2014 January 2014 December 2013
August 2013 June 2013 April 2013 March 2013 January 2013 December 2012 November
2012 October 2012 September 2012 February 2012 January 2012 December 2011


CATEGORIES

Categories Select Category Art Coffee Ebook Coffee Economics Coffee History
Comments and Reflection DISCUSSION PAPERS JURNAL PREDATOR KOLEKSI BUKU Kopi
Nusantara Legal and Free Ebook Namoura Coffee Namourapedia PERKULIAHAN Resources
Result and Research Social Uncategorized WORKING PAPERS

Free counters














FOLLOW BLOG VIA EMAIL

Enter your email address to follow this blog and receive notifications of new
posts by email.

Email Address:

Follow

Join 866 other subscribers


CREATIVE COMMONS ATTRIBUTION-NONCOMMERCIAL 4.0 INTERNATIONAL LICENSE


This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0
International License.



Top
Blog at WordPress.com.

Mr. Rows Namoura Coffee
Create a free website or blog at WordPress.com.
 * Subscribe Subscribed
    * Mr. Rows Namoura Coffee
      
      Join 275 other subscribers
      
      Sign me up
    * Already have a WordPress.com account? Log in now.

 * Privacy
 *  * Mr. Rows Namoura Coffee
    * Customize
    * Subscribe Subscribed
    * Sign up
    * Log in
    * Report this content
    * View site in Reader
    * Manage subscriptions
    * Collapse this bar

 

Loading Comments...

 

Write a Comment...
Email (Required) Name (Required) Website